7.464, Sum: "MUST"

The Linguist List linguist at tam2000.tamu.edu
Wed Mar 27 00:44:24 UTC 1996


---------------------------------------------------------------------------
LINGUIST List:  Vol-7-464. Tue Mar 26 1996. ISSN: 1068-4875. Lines:  368
 
Subject: 7.464, Sum: "MUST"
 
Moderators: Anthony Rodrigues Aristar: Texas A&M U. <aristar at tam2000.tamu.edu>
            Helen Dry: Eastern Michigan U. <hdry at emunix.emich.edu> (On Leave)
            T. Daniel Seely: Eastern Michigan U. <dseely at emunix.emich.edu>
 
Associate Editor:  Ljuba Veselinova <lveselin at emunix.emich.edu>
Assistant Editors: Ron Reck <rreck at emunix.emich.edu>
                   Ann Dizdar <dizdar at tam2000.tamu.edu>
                   Annemarie Valdez <avaldez at emunix.emich.edu>
 
Software development: John H. Remmers <remmers at emunix.emich.edu>
 
Editor for this issue: lveselin at emunix.emich.edu (Ljuba Veselinova)
 
---------------------------------Directory-----------------------------------
1)
Date:  Tue, 26 Mar 1996 15:00:40 CST
From:  edith at csd.uwm.edu (Edith A Moravcsik)
Subject:  "MUST"
 
---------------------------------Messages------------------------------------
1)
Date:  Tue, 26 Mar 1996 15:00:40 CST
From:  edith at csd.uwm.edu (Edith A Moravcsik)
Subject:  "MUST"
 
 
       On February 6, l996, I posted the following query on LINGUIST:
 
       *** Of the three sentences below, why is 1. ungrammatical but 2.
           and 3. grammatical?
 
           l. *The books sell well (in order) to raise money.
           2. The books must sell well (in order) to raise money.
           3. It is necessary that the books sell well (in order) to
              raise money. ***
 
       Sentence 1. was taken from an exercise in Liliane Haegeman's
       textbook _Introduction to government and binding theory_ (1994
       (second edition), Blackwell's, page 79). The fact that 2. was
       grammatical in spite of its minimal difference from 1. had been
       pointed out to me by William Bellin.
 
       Many thanks to the following 32 persons who responded:
 
           David Baxter
           Bill Bennett
           Ginny Brennan
           Wayles Brown
           Annabel Cormack
           Peter Daniels
           Suzette Haden Elgin
           Joseph Foster
           Frank Gladney
           Ted Harding
           Michael Hegarty
           Richard Ingham
           Roumyana Izvorski
           Graham Katz
           Marion Kee
           Luuk Lagerwerf
           Donna Lillian
           Waruno Mahdi
           Mark Mandel
           Kate McCreight
           Michael Niv
           Ellen Prince
           David Powers
           Diego Quesada
           J. Reinhardt
           Larry Rosenwald
           Marilyn Silva
           Wilbert Spooren (through Luuk Lagerwerf)
           Jack Wiedrick
           Debbie Ziegeler
           Magdalena Zoeppritz
           and a linguist who wished to remain anonymous.
 
       Below is a brief summary of the responses, structured as
       follows:
              l. Well-formedness judgments
              2. Proposed explanations
              3. Additional data with comments
              4. Literature

       l. WELL-FORMEDNESS JUDGMENTS
 
       The well-formedness judgments that I submitted were as follows:
       (numbers refer to sentence numbers):
          *1.  2.  3.
       The following comments and alternative judgments were reported:
       a/  1.  2.  3. (by a speaker of Ozark English who is also
                      fluent in American Midwestern English; however,
                      for another Ozark speaker, 1. was ill-formed)
       b/ ?1.  2.  3. (this speaker said she could get a reading for
                      1. where an implicit animate agent was present)
       c/ *1.  2.  3. (if 2. contains no "in order") but
          *1. *2.  3. (if 2. does contain "in order")
       d/ *1.  2.  3. (if 2. has the epistemic "must") but
          *1. *2.  3. (if 2. has the non-epistemic "must")
       e/ *1. ?2. *3. (2. is better if "for us" and "enough (money)"
                      are added)
       f/ *1. *2. *3. (by a speaker of Canadian (Southern Ontario)
                      English and by a speaker of American English who
                      said several others also agreed with him)
 
       2. PROPOSED EXPLANATIONS
 
       The general consensus was that 1. was ill-formed not for
       syntactic but for semantic reasons. Two alternative semantic
       conflicts were proposed as the cause:
 
          a/ One of the conditions under which an infinitival purpose
       clause can occur in a well-formed sentence is if the main
       clause contains a goal-directed action verb and, as a
       consequence, an intentional agent which is then understood as
       the subject of the purposive infinitive. In 1., this condition
       is not met: the main clause is about a non-goal-directed action
       ("sell" in its middle use) and an unintentional agent ("the
       books").
 
          b/ Another possible function of an infinitival purpose
       clause is to restrict a modal operator, such as "must", saying
       something like 'If the books are to raise money, they must sell
       well.' But in 1. there is no modal operator for the purpose
       clause to restrict.
 
       2. in turn is well-formed (even though it differs from 1. only
       by the added "must") for the following alternative reasons:
 
          A/ The "must" of 2. implies intention: it implies an
       assessment of the situation on behalf of the speaker and it
       presupposes that the speaker (or the hearer) is responsible for
       the selling of the books. Putting it differently; "must"
       is associated with an implicit external argument; by
       introducing the perspective of the speaker it suggests the
       meaning 'I find it very important that these books sell well if
       they are to raise money.' Thus, with "must", the sentence
       fulfils the condition mentioned in a/ above.

          B/ 2. is well-formed because there is a modal which the
       purpose clause can serve to restrict. 2. therefore fulfils
       the second condition, mentioned in b/ above.
 
          C/ The "must"-containing main clause in 2. expresses a
       precondition for the event referred to in the purpose clause.
       Thus, 2. means something like 'If the books sell well, money
       will be raised.'.
 
       3. ADDITIONAL DATA WITH COMMENTS
 
       4. *This car drives smoothly (in order) to increase
           sales/prevent accidents/ prevent mechanical damage...
 
           Ill-formed for the same reason as 1.
 
       5. a/ ?Max wounds easily (in order) to come across as a
              sensitive guy.
          b/ *Max wounds easily (in order) to help him make stronger.
 
          5.a/ is OK if Max "is the orchestrator of a series of public
          events where he is seen to be easily wounded" since in this
          case there is an intentional agent and goal-directed
          activity. 5.b/ is ill-formed because the agent of the
          purpose clause is different from Max.
 
       6. a/ *John must be a murderer (in order) to explain these
              facts.
          b/  John must be a murderer (in order) to ensure that Brenda
              gets away. /said in a context where a plan is being
              hatched to kill somebody/
          c/  John must register before tomorrow (in order) to take
              classes this semester.
          d/ *Rock conducts heat (in order) to maintain its chemical
              structure.
          e/  John runs fast (in order) to increase his heart rate.
 
          These sentences illustrate that regularly occurring events
          (as in 1.) as well as deductions (6.a/) and natural laws
          (6.d/) fall outside the domain of intentionality.
 
       7. a/ Eggs are broken (in order) to make omelettes.
          b/ The ship was sold to collect insurance.
          c/ The books were sold (in order) to raise money.
 
          These sentences are well-formed even though they are very
          similar to ill-formed 1. The reason is that the passive
          verbs in the main clause imply an intentional agent, which
          then is interpreted as the subject of the infinitival
          purpose clause. A middle verb in the main clause (as in 1.)
          does not similarly imply an intentional agent. The general
          point is that control is determined by thematic relations
          and not by grammatical relations.

       8. The covers must be attractive (in order) for the book to
          sell well.
 
          This sentence shows that "must" does not (always) supply an
          animate agent for the purpose clause; in this instance it
          does not since the purpose clause has an explicit non-
          animate subject!
 
       9. a/ The staff work well (in order) to raise money.
          b/ The engine runs hot (in order) to save fuel.
 
          9.a/ is well-formed even though it is similar to 1. because
          the main clause includes an intentional agent. 9.b/ is also
          well-formed because it is implied that the engine was
          designed by somebody to run hot and this person is
          understood as the subject of the purpose infinitive. It is
          possible to design a car to run hot but less possible to
          design books to sell well.
 
      10. a/ *The books were sold without reading them.
          b/  The books can be sold without reading them.
          c/ *The books might have been sold without reading them.
          d/ ?The books might sell well in order to raise money.
          e/ *The books may sell well in order to raise money,
 
          Non-epistemic modals other than "must" can also save a
          sentence like 10.a/ from ill-formedness. 10.a/ is ill-formed
          since, because of the attachment site of the adjunct, the
          external argument of the passive cannot be a controller of
          the PRO of the infinitive. 10.c/, d/, and e/ are ill-formed
          because the modals are epistemic.
 
      11. a/ *The boat sank in order to raise money.
          b/  The boat must sink in order to raise money.
          c/  It is necessary that the boat sink in order to raise
              money.
          d/ *The rock rolled down the hill in order to raise money.
          e/  The rock must roll down the hill in order to raise money.
 
          11.a/ and 11.d/ show that not only middle verbs but other
          kinds of semantically non-agentive predicates exhibit the same
          pattern.
 
      12. The Dutch translations of sentences 1.-3. are associated with
          the same well-formedness judgments as their English
          equivalents:
 
          a/ *Deze boeken verkopen goed om geld op te brengen.
          b/  Deze boeken moeten goed verkopen om geld op to brengen.
          c/  Het is noodzakelijk dat deze boeken goed verkopen om
              geld op to brengen.

      13. a/  The girl works hard (in order) to raise money.
          b/ *The girl works well (in order) to raise money.
          c/ *The girl functions well (in order) to raise money.
          d/ *The solution works well (in order) to raise money.
          e/  The girl is diligent (in order) to raise money.
 
          These sentences show that the subject of the main clause has
          to be something that may carry motivation and that engages
          in a goal-directed activity.
 
      14. The animals sell well (in order) to raise money.
 
          This sentence is ill-formed in isolation since animals
          cannot intend to raise money. But in an appropriate context,
          where animals can be construed as having intentions, the
          sentence becomes well-formed. Suppose a pet store owner is
          complaining about the indifference of the people in town
          and their unwillingness to buy pets. The animals in the
          store overhear this and make a point of acting cute and
          frisky in order to attract passsers-by. In this context, one
          can say "The animals were selling well to raise money for
          the owner."
 
      15. a/ *The book is a best-seller to raise money.
          b/  These bagels cut easily to allow for quick buttering.
          c/  The sleeves are long to show the cuffs under a jacket.
          d/  The boat was sunk to collect the insurance.
          e/ *The boat got sunk to collect the insurance.
 
          All of these sentences show if an agent is inferrable in the
          main clause, the purpose clause is appropriately added and
          the whole sentence is well-formed.
 
      16. Our subway doors close slowly (in order) to minimize the
          chances of injury. /said by company representative in sales
          pitch to city officials/
 
          This is syntactically like 1. but it is well-formed since it
          is possible for the listener to find a sentient agent
          involved whose presence justifies the purpose clause.
 
      17. a/  The books are being sold to raise money.
          b/  The books must be sold to raise (the/some/enough...)
              money.
          c/ ?It is necessary that the books be sold to raise money.
 
          These are true-passive variants of 1.-3. Once again, true
          passives involve an implied agent which makes them
          well-formed.

       4. LITERATURE  /given as cited in the responses; only a few
          additional data have been supplied by me)
 
          Carlson, 1989.
          Fox, Denny. /a paper on passives and on the _by_- phrase/
          Gross, Derek. /unpublished CLS paper/
          Hale, Kenneth and Samuel J. Kayser. 1993. "On argument
       structure and the lexical expression of syntactic relations".
       In: K. Hale and S. J. Kayser, ed., _The view from building 20_,
       53-109. Cambridge: MIT Press.
          Hegarty, Michael. l989 or later. WECOL 2.
          Jones, Charles. l985. /dissertation on syntax/ University of
       Massachusetts.
          Kehler. l995. _Interpreting cohesive forms in the context of
       discourse inference._ Harvard University Dissertation.
          Kratzer, Angelica. 1986.
          Kratzer, Angelica. 1991. "Modality". In A. von Stechow, D.
       Wunderlich (ed.), _Semantics: an international handbook of
       contemporary research_. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
          Lagerwerf, Luuk. 1995. "The implication of Dutch 'hoevel'
       (although)" _Proceedings of the Third ISSA Conference on
       Argumentation_, volume 3.
          Lascarides and Asher. 1991. "Discourse relations and
       defeasable knowledge". _Proceedings of the Association of
       Computational Linguistics_.
          Minkoff, Seth. /MIT dissertation from a couple of years ago/
       MIT WPL.
          Mishigauchi. l994. /article/ _Language_.
          Sanders, Jose. 1994. _Perspectives in narrative discourse_.
       Tilburg University Dissertation.
          Schlesinger, I.M. 1988. "The origin of relational
       categories." In Y. Levy, I.M. Schlesinger, and M.D.S. Braine
       (ed.), _Categories and processes in language acquisition_.
       121-178. Hillsdale: Erlbaum.
          Williams, E. 1985. "PRO and Subject of NP" _Natural Language
       and Linguistic Theory_, 3.
          Williams, E. 1987. "Implicit arguments, the Binding Theory,
       and Control". _Natural Language and Linguistic Theory_, 5.
 
 
 
   ************************************************************************
				 Edith A. Moravcsik
				 Department of Linguistics
			         University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee
				 Milwaukee, WI 53201-0413
                                 USA
 
				 E-mail: edith at csd.uwm.edu
				 Telephone: (414) 229-6794 /office/
					    (414) 332-0141 /home/
			         Fax: (414) 229-6258
 
 
 
 
 
					      	
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
------------------------------------------------------------------------
LINGUIST List: Vol-7-464.



More information about the LINGUIST mailing list