14.3180, Review: Syntax, Ling Theories: Epstein & Seely (2002)

LINGUIST List linguist at linguistlist.org
Thu Nov 20 16:37:33 UTC 2003


LINGUIST List:  Vol-14-3180. Thu Nov 20 2003. ISSN: 1068-4875.

Subject: 14.3180, Review: Syntax, Ling Theories: Epstein & Seely (2002)

Moderators: Anthony Aristar, Wayne State U.<aristar at linguistlist.org>
            Helen Dry, Eastern Michigan U. <hdry at linguistlist.org>

Reviews (reviews at linguistlist.org):
	Sheila Collberg, U. of Arizona
	Terence Langendoen, U. of Arizona

Home Page:  http://linguistlist.org/

The LINGUIST List is funded by Eastern Michigan University, Wayne
State University, and donations from subscribers and publishers.

Editor for this issue: Naomi Ogasawara <naomi at linguistlist.org>
 ==========================================================================
What follows is a review or discussion note contributed to our Book
Discussion Forum.  We expect discussions to be informal and
interactive; and the author of the book discussed is cordially invited
to join in.

If you are interested in leading a book discussion, look for books
announced on LINGUIST as "available for review." Then contact
Simin Karimi at simin at linguistlist.org.



=================================Directory=================================

1)
Date:  Wed, 19 Nov 2003 18:04:42 -0500 (EST)
From:  Kleanthes Grohmann <kleanthes at punksinscience.org>
Subject:  Derivation and Explanation in the Minimalist Program

-------------------------------- Message 1 -------------------------------

Date:  Wed, 19 Nov 2003 18:04:42 -0500 (EST)
From:  Kleanthes Grohmann <kleanthes at punksinscience.org>
Subject:  Derivation and Explanation in the Minimalist Program

Epstein, Samuel David and T. Daniel Seely, eds. (2002) Derivation and
Explanation in the Minimalist Program, Blackwell Publishing.

Announced at http://linguistlist.org/issues/13/13-1455.html


Kleanthes K. Grohmann, University of Cyprus

BACKGROUND

The title of this volume hits a tune similar to one that sounds
familiar to many and really goes back to the pre-minimalist era:
derivation vs. representation. It is particularly fitting, however,
for the minimalist project as laid out in considerable detail in
Chomsky (1995) and much subsequent work by Chomsky (such as Chomsky
2001) as well as many other scholars (see e.g. Epstein and Hornstein
1999b, Baltin and Collins 2001, Hendrick 2003 for collections of
recent appraisals). The way Chomsky paints the picture, the
computational system of human language, C-HL, is derivational in
nature, proceeding bottom-up by successive application of the
operation Merge with items first taken from the lexicon (the
numeration or lexical array), and then with items already merged, aka
Move. Under the copy theory of movement, syntactic objects are copied
and re-merged, accounting for movement, followed by deletion of the
lower copy (presumably for PF- reasons; see Nunes 1995, Hornstein 2001
for detailed discussion). In most ''standard'' approaches to movement,
Move (qua Copy plus Merge) also creates a chain, well known from GB,
that contains the moved element and its copy/trace.

This aspect of C-HL in particular is suspect for defenders of a
representational nature of language, casting doubt on the hybrid
character of the system to derive dependencies and also represent them
on the grounds of a very basic minimalist echo: economy. If one goal
of linguistic theory is to explain the workings of grammar in an
economical fashion -- meant both ways, an economic apparatus adhering
to Occam's razor as well as economizing nature of language itself -
why posit a two-part analysis if one is enough? The argument is that
we need some kind of representational system -- whether expressed
pseudo- derivationally as a chain or representationally as a, well,
chain -- so we should be able to dump one of them. In the case of all
but one of the contributors to the volume under review, the desire to
derive the outputs.

This is an extremely simplified exposition, of course. Among other
things, it should be noted that not all minimalist work assumes chains
as ingredients of C-HL (Hornstein 2001, Kiguchi 2002, Grohmann 2003),
that the chain-thing can be handled differently, perhaps truly
derivationally (Nunes 1995, Boeckx 2003), and that the
representational argument is not as simple as just presented (Brody
1995). But the point of this book is very clear: IF (many) researchers
agree that the system is or should be derivational, what is the
explanatory power of the system? I believe this question makes even
more sense if we see the Minimalist Program (MP) as a more or less
natural development of a good, explanatory framework, Government-and
Binding Theory (GB), a conjecture not shared by everyone, but by a
considerable part of the Principles-and-Parameters population (made
explicit in Hornstein, Nunes, and Grohmann, in progress, for
example). The rationale follows well-known inductive procedure: If GB
offered explanations and if GB was representational, can a
derivational MP provide explanations?

OVERVIEW

The editors hit the book off with their ''Introduction: On the Quest
for Explanation'' (pp. 1-18). Here they present the issue of
derivation and/or representation and resulting explanatory value in
slightly more elaborate ways than I did above; they also provide a
brief chapter-by- chapter overview. (First note to the reader: both my
presentation above and the overview below are totally independent from
Epstein and Seely's introduction.) The contributors offer eleven
chapters in alphabetical order. References are cited after endnotes
individually at the end of each chapter. Apart from Acknowledgements
(x) and a List of Contributors (xi), the book features an excellent
one-for-all index, containing subjects, names, and languages
(305-317). (Second note: given that the book appeared in 2002, it is
shocking to see that many references to work published after, say,
early 2000 have not been updated at all, something that could have
been done trivially with a more dedicated editorial eye; apart from a
general discrepancy and - continuity among the individual reference
section, this is even more striking since some authors have managed to
update a given reference X, while others cite X in its pre-published
form, which suggests that although the chapters were submitted
considerably earlier than 2002, it need not have been the final word.)

Chapter 1 by Michael Brody is ''On the Status of Representations and
Derivations'' (19-41). Here he presents aspects of his own framework,
''elegant syntax'' (a.k.a. ''mirror theory'' or ''perfect syntax;''
see especially Brody 2000), pertaining to the
representational-derivational issue. Brody's discussion revolves
around issues of ''duplication'' (in the sense of the above-mentioned
possible redundancy), ''restrictiveness'' (that duplicated systems are
by nature less restrictive), and ''explanation'' (can a derivational
approach be truly explanatory?). Slightly simplifying here again, he
also addresses weak and strong versions of both the derivational- and
representational view of grammar.

Chris Collins is still busy with ''Eliminating Labels'' (42-64) in
chapter 2, which has floated around as a (rightly so) widely cited
manuscript for a few years now and seen the glimpse of publication
daylight in 2001. The main proposal is a redefinition of Merge not in
terms of projection (where a generalized Merge(X, Y) = {X, {X, Y}}),
but a pure set (Merge(X, Y) = {X, Y}). Not being able to talk about
intermediate projection levels (X-bar) is surely a welcome result from
a bare-phrase-structure perspective, but Collins also manages to
eliminate any notion of a label, including maximal projections. He
applied his system to areas that make traditionally heavy use of
mention to labels, namely X'-Theory, selection issues, the Minimal
Link Condition, and the PF-interface. His quest for explanation in a
D- approach is the derivation of well-established generalizations in
these domains without resorting to labels.

Chapter 3 by the editors, Samuel David Epstein and T. Daniel Seely,
suggests to understand ''Rule Applications as Cycles in a Level-Free
Syntax'' (65-89). So, just as Collins got rid of all labels, Epstein
and Seely get rid of all levels. Noting difficulties with the timing
of Spell Out (in the more recent minimalist system of Chomsky 2001),
they propose a radical departure from either the original single
application (Chomsky 1995) or the multiple/cyclic application
(originally due to Uriagereka 1999, but only more widely appreciated
with Chomsky 2001 and his related work in a phase-system): Spell Out
applies after each application of an operation (''transformational
rule''). One interesting side-aspect of this truly derivational system
(getting rid of one thorn in any theoretician's eyes, the Extended
Projection Principle, for example, on principled grounds) is the
serious doubts it casts on the assumption that cyclicity is packed
into ''phases'' (see also Uriagereka 1999, Grohmann 2003).

John Frampton and Sam Gutmann develop a ''Crash-Proof Syntax''
(90-105) in chapter 4. This is the fourth largely conceptual chapter
in a row, followed directly by one more. They explore a pretty simple
question: since MP is concerned with optimal design specifications
that C-HL must meet at the (PF and LF) interfaces, couldn't there be a
way that only considers derivations that conform to these design
specifications and excludes crashing derivations in the first place?
Why do only those derivations ''win'' (over others) that don't
''crash'' (fail to meet design specifications at the interface)?
Frampton and Gutmann propose one such system that furthermore does
away with any notion of ''comparison of derivation'' and the like;
again, in an economizing setting, this makes a lot of sense (see
Uriagereka 1998, Epstein and Hornstein 1999a, Hornstein 2001, Grohmann
2003 on the relevance of economy and the form of grammar).

Norbert Hornstein and Juan Uriagereka suggest the possibility of
''Reprojections'' (106-132) in grammar in chapter 5. After a hiatus of
three chapters, Hornstein and Uriagereka mention the representation
vs.  derivation question again (see BACKGROUND above) and remark on
the difficulty of deciding on one or the other, or possibly a
combination thereof, with honesty. They set the stage for their
contribution with an important suggestion as a means of decision:
''The best kind of argument for derivations involves the need for
representations whose information is required piecemeal - being vital
at one point and unwarranted at another'' (106). This chapter deals
with one such case of ''loss of information'' (where a
representationally enriched system might really face difficulties):
reprojection. Re-what? Well, not going with Collins' definition of
Merge above (see also Hornstein and Uriagereka's revealing note 2 on
p. 129), the label L of merging two objects X and Y is either X or
Y. Based on how projectionality is derived in X'-Theory, or more
recently bare phrase structure (namely, basically in a what-we-
need-is-what-we-get kind of way), it really is either X or way, but
never both. So a VP carries the label of V merged with D just because
(simplifying again). Hornstein and Uriagereka positively evaluate the
idea that a label may change in the course of the -- well yes,
derivation, not representation. They look at the syntax of binary
quantification and come to the conclusion that ''binary quantifiers
are allowed to covertly reproject after meeting their syntactic
requirements'' (128).

Chapter 6 is provided by Richard S. Kayne who looks at ''Pronouns and
Their Antecedents'' (133-166). In line with recent research on a
movement-heavy approach to traditional construal relations (citing
Hornstein 2001, among others, but not, however, work that led to e.g.
Boeckx 2003 or Grohmann 2003, which is equally relevant to Kayne's
interests -- and has surely been around prior to deadlines pertaining
to this volume), such as Conditions A and B of Binding Theory or
control structures, Kayne develops Condition C derivationally as well
(see also Zwart's contribution below). Ultimately, he argues for a
''Big DP''-approach under which the antecedent of a given coreference
relation moves out of a structure that contains the coreferent element
as well.  The explanation coming out of this chapter is a rejection of
representational Binding Theory in favour of a derivational account.

''Scrambling, Case, and Interpretability'' (167-183) are the issues
Hisatsugu Kitahara is concerned with in chapter 7. He proposes the
first serious analysis of scrambling within the phase-based Probe-Goal
system of Chomsky (2001), appealing to the distinction between the
(new) operations Agree and Match. His approach is ''strongly
derivational'' (like so many others in this volume) in which LF
interprets Case immediately upon its licensing (previously checking,
now valuing) and deletes it. Kitahara is now on home free, solving
long-known binding-theoretic properties/-blems without invoking
mechanisms that induce a violation of (the) Inclusiveness (Condition).

Chapter 8, by James McCloskey, investigates ''Resumption, Successive
Cyclicity, and the Locality of Operations'' (184-226). As can be
expected from this scholar, the paper is empirically rich and well
presented, and it is theoretically demanding and interesting. I would
even go so far and say that this chapter is a truly beautiful piece of
work which makes heads and tails out of intricate patterns (empirical)
with an elegant explanation (theoretical). The data under discussion
are instances of non-local A'-dependencies in Irish, though the
proposal is of course more far-reaching -- it's just that English
doesn't show such complex patterns. He looks at A'-relations
(concerned with both the A'-dependencies themselves and instances of
A'-binding) that could be rendered into English as something like, to
use McCloskey's example (184), 'He's the guy that they said they
thought they wanted to hire __.' What we see in Irish is a three-way
distinct complementizer depending on which kind of A'-dependency it's
involved in (the famous 'aL', 'aN', and 'go'; see McCloskey
1990). McCloskey couches his analysis within recent extensions of MP
(e.g. Chomsky 2001) and explores in considerable detail the role of
(and issues involving) intermediate movement steps.

Norvin Richards, in chapter 9, argues for ''Very Local A'-Movement in
a Root-First Derivation'' (227-248). Working in a root-first approach
to the derivation (one implementation of a top-down, rather than
bottom- up, system), Richards explores and corroborates an interesting
prediction of an earlier paper of his: A'-movement, the traditional
least local type of movement, should in fact be very local (under
certain circumstances), much more in line with A-movement. In the
course of the discussion, Richards demonstrates that, at least in this
system, Move should also be preferred over Merge (contra Chomsky 1995
and much research that upholds something like the ''Merge over Move
Preference'' -- see also Castillo, Drury, and Grohmann 1999, and
especially Drury 1998 in a more Richards-like system, or rather one
that takes Phillips 1996 as its stepping stone). Along the way,
Richards argues in favour of dropping the need for numerations from
the theory of grammar, develops the operation Sinking, and discusses
tough- movement, vacuous movement, contained relative clauses in
Japanese, tense islands, scrambling in Persian, and extraction in
Tagalog as instances of very local A'-movement. The interesting aspect
of this chapter is that one can find explanation in derivation
regardless of whether it proceeds bottom-up or top-down.

Esther Torrego provides ''Arguments for a Derivational Approach to
Syntactic Relations Based on Clitics'' (249-268) in chapter 10. She
investigates subject-to-subject raising across experiencers in Romance
and addresses three syntactic problems associated with it, finding a
derivational solution derived from the Minimal Link Condition: Why can
subjects only raise across cliticized, but not fully nominal,
experiencers in French and Italian? Why can't they raise even across a
cliticized experiencer in Spanish?  Why can French have an expletive
subject preceding an experiencer only when the experiencer is
cliticized (also in Spanish, with a null expletive subject)? (I might
have got these questions wrong; I'm not an expert on these issues at
all, Torrego's exposition including glosses is not always the
clearest, and the ''problems'' mentioned in the beginning are never
returned to or addressed as such again; then just take these questions
as some of the questions Torrego aims to account for.) A careful
derivational understanding of the Minimal Link Condition explains
these cases, while the condition as laid out representationally
(possibly as stated originally in Chomsky 1995, at least at first
glance), fails to do so.

In the final chapter of the book, Jan-Wouter Zwart considers ''Issues
Relating to a Derivational Theory of Binding'' (269-304). It is
similar to Kayne's contribution in spirit, but adopts the strictly
derivational approach to C-HL of Epstein et al. (1998). In a way,
though, it can be thought of as a companion piece to Kayne's chapter,
since Zwart deals with those relations that Kayne is not concerned
with, namely strictly local anaphor dependencies. In a nutshell, Zwart
analyses locally bound anaphors as ''the marked Spell Out of a generic
variable referential element (''PRONOUN'')'' (294) with the
coreferentiality property acquired in the course of the derivation
(making this type of Spell Out different from the notion of Copy Spell
Out argued for in both Hornstein 2001 and Grohmann 2003, again without
mention of either work). The big idea to take home here is that
coreferentiality is not the result of an interpretive mechanism, or an
interpretive procedure itself, but ''a function of the operation
Merge'' (295) - in other words, it receives a truly derivational
explanation.

CLOSURE

I already threw in my general impressions of the book and some
shortcomings (mainly on the editorial/literature side: shortcomings in
updating references, lack of coherence in citing references, and
absence of some relevant references). I also added my own salt to some
of the chapters above. Therefore, I really want to close with only one
comment. Now that we have seen such a fine collection of arguments for
explanation in derivation, maybe the next collection could re-address
the question of representation vs. derivation in a new light (beyond
Lasnik 2001 and more generally the, in this respect, disappointing
Part I of Baltin and Collins' 2001 rather sensationally titled
''Derivation versus Representation''). It has become clear that this
question doesn't have a simple answer; and in the present volume,
Hornstein and Uriagereka are particularly honest in this respect: ''if
reprojection should prove to occur grammatically, it would argue that
grammars are (at least in part) derivational systems'' (106). Maybe
it's not even desirable to have one. But it would be interesting if we
collectively could address this question one day without rhetoric or
prejudice.  Epstein and Seely's volume strongly suggests that (pardon
my Shakespeare) not all is rotten in the State of Derivation.

In sum, despite the negative aspects I managed to throw in here and
there, I think this is an excellent addition to any theoretically
minded linguist's library (though minimalistically tempted
syntacticians may get most out of it). I think it's a healthy sign if
some questions are asked over and over again. Good thing about the
contributors to this book is that they don't ask too many old
questions. They just take some aspects of the theory and run with it,
(by and large) each for him- and herself. The result is an intriguing
potpourri of some of the hottest researchers around today. Definitely
worth one's time.

REFERENCES

Baltin, Mark R. and Chris Collins, eds. (2001) The Handbook of
Contemporary Syntactic Theory. Oxford: Blackwell.

Boeckx, Cedric (2003) Islands and Chains. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

Brody, Michael (1995) Lexico-Logical Form. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press.

Brody, Michael (2000) Mirror Theory: Syntactic Representation in
Perfect Syntax. Linguistic Inquiry 31, 29-56.

Castillo, Juan Carlos, John Drury, and Kleanthes K. Grohmann (1999)
Merge over Move and the Extended Projection Principle. University of
Maryland Working Papers in Linguistics 8, 63-103.

Chomsky, Noam (1995) The Minimalist Program. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press.

Chomsky, Noam (2001) Derivation by Phase. In Michael Kenstowicz (ed),
2001. Ken Hale. A Life in Language. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1-52.

Drury, John Edward (1998) The Promise of Derivations: Atomic Merge &
Multiple Spell-Out. Groninger Arbeiten zur germanistischen Linguistik
42, 61-108.

Epstein, Samuel David, Erich M. Groat, Ruriko Kawashima & Hisatsugu
Kitahara (1998) A Derivational Approach to Syntactic
Relations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Epstein, Samuel David & Norbert Hornstein (1999a) Introduction. In
Epstein & Hornstein (1999b), ix-xviii.

Epstein, Samuel David & Norbert Hornstein, eds. (1999b) Working
Minimalism. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Grohmann, Kleanthes K. (2003) Prolific Domains: On the Anti-Locality
of Movement Dependencies. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. [November 2003]

Hendrick, Randall, ed. (2003) Minimalist Syntax. Oxford: Blackwell.

Hornstein, Norbert (2001) Move! A Minimalist Theory of Construal.
Oxford: Blackwell.

Hornstein, Norbert, Jairo Nunes, and Kleanthes K. Grohmann (in
progress) Understanding Minimalism: An Introduction to Minimalist
Syntax. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Kiguchi, Hirohisa (2002) Syntax Unchained. Doctoral dissertation,
University of Maryland, College Park.

Lasnik, Howard (2001) Derivation vs. Representation in Modern
Transformational Syntax. In Baltin & Collins (2001), 197-217.

McCloskey, James (1990) Resumptive Pronouns, A'-Binding and Levels of
Representation in Irish. In Randall Hendrick, ed. Syntax and Semantics
23: Syntax of the Modern Celtic Languages. New York: Academic Press,
199-248.

Nunes, Jairo (1995) The Copy Theory of Movement and Linearization of
Chains in the Minimalist Program. Doctoral dissertation, University of
Maryland, College Park.

Phillips, Colin (1996) Order and Structure. Doctoral dissertation,
MIT.

Uriagereka, Juan (1998) Rhyme and Reason: An Introduction to
Minimalist Syntax. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Uriagereka, Juan (1999) Multiple Spell Out. In Epstein & Hornstein
(1999b), 251-282.

ABOUT THE REVIEWER

I'm interested in syntactic theory (esp. within Principles-and-
Parameters approaches) and comparative syntax (esp. Germanic, Romance,
Slavic, Greek) and have worked on different topics, such as wh-
constructions, left dislocation and resumption, cliticization, and
reverse locality effects, what I call "anti-locality." You find
personal and professional information about me on my homepage at
http://www.punksinscience.org/kleanthes.  For more on PUNKS IN SCIENCE,
a project I'm involved in with Jeff Parrott from Georgetown
University, please go to http://www.punksinscience.org , laugh, and get
in touch with us. (The manifesto is pretty cool though, and we ARE
serious!) I'm also involved with the Ask-A-Linguist service offered by
LINGUIST List, where I am a member of the expert panel. Two previous
reviews of mine appeared on LINGUIST List: Three Types of Extraction,
by Paul Postal  http://linguistlist.org/issues/10/10-934.html , and On
the Nature of the Syntax-Phonology Interface: Cliticization and
Related Phenomena, by Zeljko Boskovic
http://linguistlist.org/issues/12/12-2776.html


---------------------------------------------------------------------------

If you buy this book please tell the publisher or author
that you saw it reviewed on the LINGUIST list.

---------------------------------------------------------------------------
LINGUIST List: Vol-14-3180



More information about the LINGUIST mailing list