16.1890, Review: Ling Theories/Syntax: Seuren (2004)

LINGUIST List linguist at linguistlist.org
Sun Jun 19 22:13:39 UTC 2005


LINGUIST List: Vol-16-1890. Sun Jun 19 2005. ISSN: 1068 - 4875.

Subject: 16.1890, Review: Ling Theories/Syntax: Seuren (2004)

Moderators: Anthony Aristar, Wayne State U <aristar at linguistlist.org>
            Helen Aristar-Dry, Eastern Michigan U <hdry at linguistlist.org>
 
Reviews (reviews at linguistlist.org) 
        Sheila Dooley, U of Arizona  
        Terry Langendoen, U of Arizona  

Homepage: http://linguistlist.org/

The LINGUIST List is funded by Eastern Michigan University, Wayne
State University, and donations from subscribers and publishers.

Editor for this issue: Naomi Ogasawara <naomi at linguistlist.org>
================================================================  

What follows is a review or discussion note contributed to our 
Book Discussion Forum. We expect discussions to be informal and 
interactive; and the author of the book discussed is cordially 
invited to join in. If you are interested in leading a book 
discussion, look for books announced on LINGUIST as "available 
for review." Then contact Sheila Dooley at collberg at linguistlist.org. 

===========================Directory==============================  

1)
Date: 19-Jun-2005
From: Kleanthes Grohmann < kleanthi at ucy.ac.cy >
Subject: Chomsky's Minimalism 

	
-------------------------Message 1 ---------------------------------- 
Date: Sun, 19 Jun 2005 18:08:41
From: Kleanthes Grohmann < kleanthi at ucy.ac.cy >
Subject: Chomsky's Minimalism 
 

AUTHOR: Seuren, Pieter A. M. 
TITLE: Chomsky's Minimalism
PUBLISHER: Oxford University Press
YEAR: 2004
Announced at http://linguistlist.org/issues/15/15-2850.html


Kleanthes K. Grohmann, University of Cyprus

_Chomsky's Minimalism_ is an ingenuous title for a book that will 
undoubtedly polarize readers: It is aimed to be a substantial critique of 
the theoretical-conceptual foundations and scientific methodology 
underlying the Minimalist Program (in particular, and I will address this 
point below, Chomsky 1995) and its methodological and empirical 
shortcomings.

However, since the contents bear little resemblance to what one MIGHT 
expect, it is also an unfortunate title. Take _Chomsky's Universal 
Grammar_ (Cook & Newson 1996), for example, which is the main title of an 
introductory textbook to the kind of "Chomskyan linguistics" Pieter A. M. 
Seuren has been criticizing for quite some time (see e.g. Seuren 1996, 
1998, 2001 for book-length treatments that express his 'anti-Chomskyan' 
stance at varying length). By analogy, an innocent reader, a novice 
linguist, or a casual catalogue browser might assume that he or she would 
be dealing with a book that goes one step beyond Cook & Newson's 
introduction to the Government-and-Binding Theory (GB), the best approach 
to the Principles-and-Parameters Theory (P&P) that formalizes a specific 
implementation of Universal Grammar (UG), and introduces to the reader the 
most current version of the generative endeavor -- the one that has become 
known as the Minimalist Program or minimalism. Perhaps a sub-title 
like 'Not an introduction', "once jokingly proposed" by the author (Pieter 
Seuren, personal communication), would have been a good idea after all.

This said, if one knows (of) the author, one can be pretty sure what to 
expect, so matters might be simple after all. (This includes, by the way, 
the eloquent style of writing: even if one doesn't agree with what Seuren 
says, how he says it is a true pleasure to read -- something I am 
unfortunately unable to reflect or reciprocate in this review.)

STRUCTURE

It becomes clear very early on that this book is not an introduction to 
minimalism -- nor is it a (favorable or critical) explanatory commentary 
on it. It is in fact a highly provocative and rhetorically loaded negative 
critique. One only needs to consult the back cover with Geoffrey Pullum's 
praise of this book as a "comprehensive and incisive critique of the most 
influential confidence trick in the history of modern linguistics." Or 
take the publisher's / author's synopsis of the contents as criticism of a 
research program that "fails to satisfy the basic criteria for sound 
scientific work" and manifests "the cult surrounding Chomsky and 
Minimalism more generally."

Let me stay with the book's exteriors for one more paragraph. If there is 
something I am certainly not, it's art historian or critic. But I was 
fascinated by the cover art ("Landscape with mountain chapel" by the Dutch 
surrealist painter Albert Carel Willink) and the imagery it provoked in 
me. So I asked my wife, who is no art historian either (and not even a 
linguist), to see what kind of impression it evoked in her. The response 
was very interesting and probably something Seuren could have had in mind 
himself. Her initial reaction was "It's go-go-go -- and then what?" 
(presumably commenting on the steps that lead into the chapel with no end 
point and the cave opening higher up the mountain). She felt that the 
painting itself expressed something very old and something very modern at 
the same time. But she also observed that something was missing and it 
wasn't quite clear what. So, from the selling point of view, this book 
seems to deliver a clear message.

In this review I want to show that such imagery reflects minimalism to a 
certain point, but that one doesn't need to take this as a negative 
reflection of the research program. Rather, as has been stressed over and 
over again by Noam Chomsky himself alongside a large number of linguists 
(see Hornstein, Nunes & Grohmann, in press, for a clear presentation along 
these lines), minimalism is a research program that follows its P&P-
predecessor in many ways, but tries to minimize the humungous apparatus GB 
required. (Incidentally, this includes minimization of levels of 
representation and of internal modules, both vehemently criticized by 
Seuren, but perhaps not for the most convincing reasons or even in a 
relevant manner, as pointed out below.) Moreover, and this is the exciting 
part of the project, it opens up new questions about the nature of 
language and an adequate description thereof.

So, to pick up on the imagery of the cover, "it's go-go-go" since 
minimalism offers many new research areas, and at the same time there is 
no end in sight (yet!). This is not bad at all: All it says is that 
linguists can now ask interesting new questions, explore them in their 
glorious detail -- and develop the program in such a way that it becomes a 
theory of language one day. This theory will undoubtedly look VERY 
different from today's Minimalist Program. In fact, the Minimalist Program 
has undergone tremendous change already (something completely ignored by 
Seuren, as also pointed out below). There is no 'minimalist theory' yet, 
but some of us are working on it. And while contributions by Pieter Seuren 
and the like (e.g. Rudolf Botha, Paul Postal, or Geoffrey Pullum, all 
frequently quoted in this book, often from "personal communication") can 
be much appreciated if they are substantial and constructive, negative 
rhetoric and continued grief with the demise of generative semantics (and 
here a plethora of like-minded authors could be listed) have little room 
for sympathy and don't contribute to advanced understanding of the issues. 
For a critical perspective, one might want to consult something like 
Shalom Lappin and David Johnson's work (Lappin & Johnson 1997, 1999) that 
presents the concepts and workings of minimalism as intended and offers a 
critique of specific issues rather than with the present text and related 
ones. (Unfortunately, the latter category also includes ill-guided 
debates, in my opinion, such as the one initiated by the two 
aforementioned scholars and Robert Levine in Natural Language & Linguistic 
Theory a few years ago.)

For purposes of this review, each chapter will be presented in a concise 
paragraph including the sections contained in it (minus the 'Conclusion' 
sections of chapters 2 to 8), followed by some of the thoughts it stirred 
in me. Length considerations led me to dwell on some chapters more than on 
others -- for perhaps obvious reasons, I chose to concentrate on chapters 
1, 2, and 8. There is much more to say, of course, and someone else would 
surely focus on different issues; what follows is what I focus on for lack 
of a different perspective.

The following outline is intended to help the reader assign title, length, 
and topic to each chapter discussed below:

The preface (pp. v-vi) sets the stage: for those who are not familiar with 
Seuren, this book is written by someone who has given up following the 
direction of linguistic theorizing Chomsky has developed since 
the 'generative semantics era' of the early 1970s, and this background is 
reflected on virtually every page of the book.
  1 -- Chapter 1 is a comprehensive 'Introduction' (pp. 3-30) to this book 
in which Seuren lays out why he does what he does.
  2 -- 'The Mechanism of the MP under Scrutiny' (pp. 31-50) forms chapter 
2, Seuren's idiosyncratic presentation of the theoretical-conceptual 
foundation of minimalism.
  3 -- Chapter 3 deals with 'The Language Faculty' (pp. 51-96), and Seuren 
lays out what Chomsky(ans) take(s) it to be, why that is misguided, and 
how one should really think of it.
  4 -- Chapter 4 offers 'Questions of Method and Adequacy' (pp. 97-124) -- 
yes, it tells the reader that Chomsky's methods are unsound and don't meet 
scientific adequacy.
  5 -- 'What Is Functional about the MP?' (pp. 125-149) is asked in 
chapter 5 and answered in the negative, with particular emphasis given to 
(perfect) language design.
  6 -- 'What Is Conceptually Necessary about the MP?' (pp. 125-149) is 
asked in chapter 6 and answered equally in the negative, where the two 
main building blocks are the architecture assumed in minimalism and the 
motivation of the "displacement property" (i.e. what has become known 
analytically as 'movement').
  7 -- Chapter 7 addresses 'Surface-Driven Elements of Semantic 
Interpretation' (pp. 169-190) and Seuren's arguments against minimalism's 
abolishment of a concept like "surface structure" on the grounds of 
interplay with interpretation.
  8 -- The concluding chapter 8 aims to disclose 'The Embarrassment of 
Evidence' (pp. 191-230), which turns out to be an embarrassing discussion 
of syntactic analysis.
The book is rounded off with the references (pp. 231-238) and an index 
(pp. 239-244) containing authors, languages, and terms.

DISCUSSION

CHAPTER 1 opens with the 'Stated aim': "to show that Noam Chomsky's latest 
version of his linguistic theory, recently published as _The Minimalist 
Program_ (MP) (1995), though presented as the crowning achievement of the 
Chomskyan version of generative grammar, is in fact the clearest possible 
demonstration that that version is fundamentally flawed" (p. 1). Do we 
really need to say more? The rhetorical style of the book connects to this 
opening sentence seamlessly. The remaining sections of this introductory 
chapter are 'The hard truth about the MP', 'Further 
misgivings', 'Presentation and terminology', 'Mysterious paradigm mixing', 
and 'Empirical issues'. Here Seuren paves the way for his extensive 
discussion and critique of the methodology behind Chomsky's minimalism (as 
opposed to an 'alternative minimalism', for example).

As Seuren states in the Preface, he understands that "the focus of 
attention [in minimalism] has shifted from theorizing about grammar 
writing to the loftier level of methodological reflection" (v). 
Consequently, he spends considerable time dissecting issues of contention 
with such a "loftier level" throughout the book, introduced in CHAPTER 1. 
He does so in particular in the chapters I will not discuss in any depth 
below.

My reasons for this decision are simple. By concentrating on Seuren's -- 
often misguided or misinformed -- portrayal of minimalist concepts and 
analysis as well as his strong rhetoric, I believe I can highlight much 
better what goes wrong in the book. Recall that by virtue of its title, 
one can reasonably assume this book to be a critique of minimalism as a 
whole. At least I do so and in the absence of an alternative review, stick 
to it. If Seuren's main goal was to denounce the methodology behind 
Chomsky's minimalist approach, he could have indicated this in the title 
or pursued it more consequently by not attempting to discuss the 
theoretical apparatus. Since half the chapters deal with technical issues 
in one way or another, and since there are limitations of space, I believe 
my decision is well justified.

To return to CHAPTER 1, part of the "hard truth" argument is that "in the 
wider circles of intellectuals" (i.e. outside linguistics), "there is a 
widespread belief that Chomskyan linguistics is the only serious form of 
scientific syntax" (p. 7). And footnote 1 on this page, as sprinkled 
throughout the book, picks out a random example which Seuren comments with 
the words that "[o]ne could cite numerous other authors who put blind 
faith in Chomsky's linguistics without, apparently, having actually 
studied his works." I'm sure many readers will agree that a 'Chomskyan 
linguist' would jump up and exclaim, "I wish!" -- the impact on non-
linguistic (biological, psychological, or any other) realms of 
science "Chomskyan linguistics" has had over the past 50 years is by far 
not as deeply-rooted as Seuren and other critics like to make it sound 
(and even in linguistics, generativists don't constitute the majority if 
we look at numbers world-wide). I don't see too many core "Chomskyan 
linguistics" courses taught in psychology or biology departments, not even 
an exegesis of the most fundamental concepts generative grammar has 
developed in the past five decades. And most 'current' references to 
generative grammar provided by non-generativists and non-linguists usually 
stop in 1965, or the early 1970s at best.

In addition, Seuren is guilty of his own accusations. Most relevant for 
the present review is the fact that Seuren sets out to 
criticize "Chomsky's minimalism" (as the title promises), but in reality 
the book is just, in Seuren's words, a critique of Chomsky's "_The 
Minimalist Program_ (MP) (1995):" to refer to this as the "latest version 
of his linguistic theory" (p. 3) and the 'definitive minimalism' (my term) 
some 10 years after publication indicates that Seuren criticizes an entire 
approach "without, apparently, having actually studied his works." As any 
recently trained student of "Chomskyan linguistics" is aware, MP has been 
followed up by a number of papers in which Chomsky clarifies, modifies, 
and extends the program laid out in 1995, in particular Chomsky (2000b, 
2001, 2004, 2005) of which the first three should have been available to 
Seuren before the final draft of his book. Since he cites work dated 2003, 
a 2001 manuscript published as Chomsky (2004) could have been accessed -- 
and studied -- easily. Moreover, _The Minimalist Program_ -- to repeat, a 
first sketch of a new direction in research -- contains four chapters, two 
of which are commonly taken to be precursors to minimalism, not minimalist 
contributions in and of themselves (chapters 1 and 2, which appeared as 
Chomsky & Lasnik 1993 and Chomsky 1991, respectively).

CHAPTER 2 tries to present 'Some "guiding ideas"' of MP and offers 'A 
closer inspection of the "computational system"' (in particular, the 
operations Select, Merge, and Move as well as the concepts Reference Set 
and Numeration).

Apart from the fact that no post-1995 reference of Chomsky's (or anyone 
else's!) work on theoretical issues in a minimalist setting has been 
consulted, giving this chapter (and the entire book) a rather outdated 
feel, Seuren does not seem to have understood the mechanics presented in 
MP all that well. (And no, I do not consider the works he does mention, 
Chomsky (1998, 2000a, 2002), relevant in this respect; neither do I accept 
the author's stated aim, reiterated in personal communication, to look 
at "the loftier level of methodological reflection" as a valid reason -- 
as mentioned above, Seuren could have just abstained from an inclusion of 
the technicalities altogether.) This begins on a trivial level with the 
continued use of the term "human language computational system" (which 
Chomsky calls CHL for "computational system of human language") inside 
double quotes, suggesting either a quotation of Chomsky's use (in which 
case it's mistaken) or an apprehension towards the term (in which case 
it's not clear why he doesn't stick to Chomsky's term).

But there are also some technical problems in Seuren's presentation. When 
he claims, for example, that "[n]o argument is offered for the implicit 
assumption ([Chomsky] 1995: 243 and elsewhere) that branchings resulting 
from Merge should be binary" (p. 34), the reader might get the impression 
that this is a novelty within syntactic theorizing proposed first within 
minimalism. Binary branching has been a standard assumption in P&P-
approaches, or "Chomskyan linguistics," since at least Kayne (1984) -- a 
source cited and discussed as early as chapter 1 of _The Minimalist 
Program_ (Chomsky 1995: 61-62). Binary branching itself thus need not be 
re-introduced and -justified; the existing literature is large enough and 
those readers of MP that are interested in it, will be familiar with the 
relevant literature or at least willing to read up on it. If Seuren's 
point is that binarity necessarily holding of the technical operation 
Merge is not clearly enough argued for, he may want to read Chomsky's 
justification for a bare phrase structure approach again and familiarize 
himself with Chomsky's adoption of set theoretic argumentation. If this is 
not formal enough either, or simply wrong in Seuren's opinion, he may say 
so and offer his arguments. For clearer presentation, he may also (read 
and) refer to the first two papers on phases (Chomsky 2000, 2001, 
circulated in manuscript form in 1998 and 1999, respectively), in which 
Chomsky sheds enough light on the issue to either fully understand the why 
or to reject the approach altogether -- but this can be reviewed or 
criticized in better ways than Seuren's off-hand remark provides. 

The same goes for Seuren's discussion of labels. The question what serves 
as the new constituent label when A and B are merged, the MP answer is 
either A or B: {G, {A, B}} with G = A or G = B. Seuren considers an option 
that was not entertained by Chomsky (who did offer two alternative 
conclusions -- intersection and union of A and B, respectively --  and 
rejecting both, as correctly reported by Seuren): the new label is neither 
A nor B, "an option grammar cannot do without" (p. 35). Even if we leave 
endocentricity issues aside, a hallmark concept in linguistic theorizing 
predating both "Chomskyan linguistics" and minimalism (cf. Harris 1951: 
275-276, Lyons 1968: 231-235), Seuren's option is still not compatible 
with the Inclusiveness Condition (Chomsky 1995: 228) -- applied to 
minimalism, I refer the interested reader in particular to sections 2.4 
and 6.2 of Hornstein, Nunes & Grohmann (in press). Likewise, even if one 
agrees with Seuren's claim just quoted, a formulation in terms 
of "proposition" or "predicate" as he does (see also his sections 3.5.1 
and 6.2.1) doesn't seem fruitful in light of independent minimalist 
assumptions. Among other things, these concepts are not primitives of the 
theory. In any case, a slightly more detailed discussion beyond the three 
paragraphs offered might have been useful to determine whether Chomsky's 
(and all his 'followers'') choice was justified, partially correct, or 
totally wrong.

Seuren also criticizes the other important operation first clearly 
formulated in minimalism, Select (which takes a lexical item from the 
Numeration and enters it into the syntactic computation, the derivation). 
He wants to cast doubt on its purported being "conceptually necessary" 
with the help of Paul Postal's observation ("personal communication") that 
a sentence such as 'The French word for milk is 'lait'' could never be 
generated: "In the Select-and-Merge setup, sentences containing such ad 
hoc words could never be generated, since such words are not in the 
English lexicon. The entire Select-and-Merge system thus seems ill-
conceived" (p. 34). The 'argumentation' makes me wonder. Does this 
particular type of case -- which involves much more than a sketch of a 
minimalist approach to linguistic theory can reasonably set out to 
accomplish (presumably, issues of interlanguage, multi-lingual lexicons, 
and so on) -- now render the entire system "ill-conceived"? I leave the 
judgment to the reader. (One could also mention in this context, as Winnie 
Lechner points out to me, that metalinguistic reference is possible to 
everything that can be written, not only to parts of the lexicon unique to 
a particular language. In other words, there must be a function which 
takes as input everything that can be expressed in writing and imports it 
into the lexicon.)

Other lamentations of Seuren's include the complaint that "on p. 155 [of 
Chomsky 1995 -- note to the reader: this is the pre-minimalist chapter 2] 
it is suggested that existential 'there' should be considered 'an LF-
affix', a kind of element not mentioned before" (p. 38). One might point 
out that GB enjoyed a very similar analysis of anaphors (cf. Lebeaux 1983, 
Chomsky 1986), so this concept is anything but new. Later on in the book, 
Seuren attacks the analysis of expletive 'there' (and existential 
constructions in general) within "Chomskyan linguistics" further. One may 
not share Chomsky's insistence on constantly overhauled analyses 
of 'there', but one surely has to admire the consequence with which 
theoretical advancements are followed through and applied to this 
construction, which has gained notoriety for exactly this reason. None of 
the elegance and technical finesse managed to secure Seuren's 
appreciation -- or reflection in the book.

This chapter contains a large number of bones I have to pick, most of 
which I cannot discuss here for length considerations. Regarding the 
Reference Set, for example, Seuren may be pleased to learn that this 
concept seems to have been given up around 1997 (see some papers collected 
in Wilder, Gärtner & Bierwisch 1997 for discussion). Likewise, the 
Numeration has evolved into the (Lexical) Array since Chomsky (2000) -- 
whether his original 'doubts' (if one can characterize thus his loose 
musings) disappear, however, is a different question. Other issues of 
contention include Seuren's derivational tree diagram (Figure 2.1 on p. 
38, adapted from Johnson & Lappin 1997: 282) and the ensuing discussion 
which highlights gaps in his technical understanding of the core 
minimalist concepts (Select, Merge, Move, and Spell-Out).

On a more philosophical level, Seuren addresses some interesting issues 
that "Chomskyan linguistics" faces quite independently of 'minimalism' 
(such as questions about evolution and exaptation of language, language 
acquisition as instantaneous development, or the cognitive/grammatical 
distinction, for example). Here one may choose to agree or disagree with 
Seuren -- but the style of presentation does unfortunately not invite 
readers like myself to take the content all that seriously.

CHAPTER 3 contains five main sections: 'Principles and Parameters: a 
historical note', 'Modularity and the random-generator 
position', 'Chomsky's ambiguous realism', 'Instantaneous language 
evolution', and 'An alternative view of the language faculty'.

One of the most interesting aspects of this chapter is Seuren's criticism 
of the architectural reduction of levels of interpretation. Where MP tries 
to reduce the four GB levels by eliminating D- and S-structure (leaving 
just Logical Form and Phonetic Form), Seuren argues that there should in 
fact be four interface levels: (i) "[t]he output end of the thought-
producing machinery," (ii) "[t]he output end of the lexicon," (iii) "[t]he 
output end of the grammar module," and (iv) "[t]he output end of the 
phonetic-orthographic machinery." However, since the chapter is, as all 
others, phrased in such an attacking manner on Chomsky(an linguistics), it 
is hard to see how, if at all, Seuren's sound architectural ideas could be 
made fit into a minimalist model -- or even in how far, if at all, these 
offer a challenge.

CHAPTER 4 is a provocative discussion of or attack on 'What can confirm or 
disconfirm a paradigm?', 'Chomsky as a higher authority', 'Ecologism and 
formalism', and 'What to do with evidence?'.

CHAPTER 5 attacks the 'The minimalist version of functionalism' and 
asks 'How perfect is language?'. The section heading 'Optimal language 
design and model building: the "fable"' speaks for itself. Seuren then 
addresses 'Language and communication' and attempts to show in which 
ways 'The minimalist program is not minimalist'. 'Why choices? The case of 
Mauritian Creole' is followed by 'Sociolinguistic factors' that should be 
taken into account.

CHAPTER 6 is an attempt to justify an answer in the negative to two 
questions: 'Conceptual motivation for the random generator?' and 'Is 
the "displacement property" conceptually motivated?'.

CHAPTER 7 is mostly empirical. Once 'The question stated' is on the table, 
Seuren goes on to attack analytical shortcomings of "Chomsky's Minimalism" 
by considering 'Focusing strategies', 'Presuppositions', and 'Operator 
scope'.

The section headings describe the content of CHAPTERS 4 to 7 very well. In 
fact, one might be tempted to take these chapters, "the loftier level of 
methodological reflection" proper, to be the core of the book. If that is 
so, my decision to concentrate on the other three chapters (plus CHAPTER 8 
addressed below) may not have been the wisest. However, the chapters I do 
discuss offer most for the direction pursued in this review -- and they 
address issues I happen to understand best and know more about. As a 
consequence, I was able to point to a number of misunderstandings and -
interpretations on Seuren's side regarding the technical implementations 
and the real conceptual aims of MP. To lay out the methodology underlying 
minimalism that Seuren takes issue with might deserve a separate review -- 
it simply cannot be integrated into the present one which concentrates on 
exposing and clarifying Seuren (mis)presentation of MP in other areas.

The chapters I am skipping over ever so gently contain mostly well-known 
quibbles with "Chomskyan linguistics" -- these are neither specific to 
minimalism nor new in any way, but in fact go back to the early 1970s, 
when scholars like Seuren got upset with the post-Aspects model and 
the 'generative semantics war' (which in and of itself is arguably not the 
best way to put it, but since I wasn't around at the time, who am I to 
talk?). And unfortunately, the reader finds a lot of Chomsky-bashing (as 
becomes clear from the section headings). Other, perhaps less known, 
quibbles concern Seuren's interpretation of the history of science, with 
particular reference to the figures mentioned most prominently by Chomsky 
himself (Galileo and Descartes, but also Copernicus, Newton, and Darwin) 
and the relevance of Cartesian investigation to linguistic methodology. 

They also contain some data discussion (continued in the final chapter 8) 
in which Seuren wants to dismantle any viability of minimalist analysis on 
the basis of a few facts about language. These include prepositional 
adjuncts (section 4.1.1) and operator scope (section 7.4). I pick out 
these two issues for the simple reason that Seuren uses them 'best' to 
show how inadequate minimalism is, and because he cross-references both 
sections, in particular the idiosyncratic take he adopts on these two 
constructions. In section 4.1.1, Seuren offers an incomprehensible nine-
page treatment of prepositional adjuncts within his own 
framework, "semantic syntax" (Seuren 1996), while, at the same time, 
leaving the reader in the dark as to why prepositional adjuncts would 
constitute such disastrous empirical counter-evidence to a minimalist 
approach. (And even if one contends with Seuren, reinforced in personal 
communication, that he "do[es] not pick out [these constructions] to show 
the inadequacy of the MP but to show the superior adequacy of [his] 
Semantic Syntax," one wonders why he chose to include them in a book that 
is apparently mainly concerned with "the loftier level of methodological 
reflection.")

The three-page discussion of operator scope -- and in particular, the fact 
that scoping elements must be present at LF ("in the logico-semantic 
analysis") -- highlights Seuren's motives once again: "[t]his point is 
implicitly recognized in May (1977), where the rule schema of Operator 
Lowering, developed in the framework of generative semantics, is simply 
reversed into Operator Raising (but without attribution)" (188). (In note 
1 on p. 171, Seuren attributes these discoveries to Lakoff (1971) and 
McCawley (1972).) He continues noting with interest that "the 
determination of operator scope is not mentioned in Chomsky's later 
writings." Somewhat flippantly but with reference to Seuren's own words, I 
would like to respond, "Come on, read "Chomsky's later writings" for a 
change!"

CHAPTER 8 is a continuation of the analytical shortcomings addressed in 
the previous chapter. Here Seuren investigates in some more 
detail 'Deletion and Raising in infinitival complements', various 'Copying 
phenomena', and the infamous 'Existential 'there''.

It starts very nicely with a footnote in which Seuren challenges 
minimalists (or so one could understand this note) that "the burden of 
proof lies with those who wish to deny surface structure as a level of 
representation, not with us" (192). Au contraire (whether or not this is 
in the lexicon of an English speaker), the burden of proof lies with those 
who wish to continue believing in S(urface)-structure as a level of 
representation! At least, so one must argue in criticizing minimalism in 
its own right, as a continuation of the successful P&P-approach of GB with 
its stated aims. In GB, S-structure was solely motivated theory-
internally, as Chomsky (1995: chap. 2) recaps (for a concise discussion, 
see e.g. chapter 2 of Hornstein, Nunes & Grohmann, in press). If Seuren 
means his own (or other continuations from the generative semantics era or 
the Aspects-model) understanding of S-structure, call it "surface 
structure," then we can't easily come to a decision -- nor can we easily 
compare the two. GB S-structure and Seuren's "surface structure" simply 
have different formal properties and hence a different standing in the 
respective approaches. Pitting these two notions against one another 
absolves anyone from providing a "burden of proof" -- at this point, 
without further discussion (on a technical level, which Seuren does not 
provide), it's comparing apples and pears.

A lot more can be said on the 'disastrous' empirical evidence against MP 
that Seuren offers (see section headings), where he ignores minimalist 
work on raising and inflected infinitives in Portuguese, exceptional Case-
marking/subject-to-object raising in Balkan subjunctives, purported bans 
on rightward movement, and so on. Or even the claim that, since "[c]opying 
is a widespread phenomenon in the languages of the world," "it finds no 
place at all in the MP" (216). Once again, Seuren's corpus of material 
under discussion (which is basically limited to Chomsky 1995), a book of 
420 pages (including references and index) simply cannot provide the 
motivation behind minimalism, the conceptualization of the program, the 
technical basics, and an exhaustive analysis of all facts found in human 
language(s). This is why _The Minimalist Program_ is a comprehensive 
presentation of a minimalist approach to linguistic theory which can be 
extended, adopted, and amended to find a satisfactory treatment of all 
this -- collectively, by all linguists interested. And this is indeed what 
some of us are working towards.

I'd rather close with rebutting an(other) utterly unnecessary ad hominem 
attack Seuren couldn't hold back. In the context of 'believe' 
vs. 'expect', Seuren fights with an answer to the question why the first 
is only an ECM verb, while the second can also be a control verb. He can't 
find one and comments his frustration: "No answer is provided. One fears 
that the author is simply forgetful, or careless" (205). This is followed 
by a wonderful footnote, which I quote in its totality:

"Some carelessness is apparent anyway on the same p. 345 [of Chomsky 
(1995)], where, in the same context, the sentence (172b) 'I expect someone 
to leave early' is discussed. Five lines below the example presented, one 
reads: "In the ECM structure (172b), H [the relevant Case-assigning head] 
assigns no case, so 'John' raises to the checking domain of Agro 
[Agreement for object] in the matrix clause." A little care would have 
shown the author that, for once, the sentence isn't about 'John', but 
about 'someone'." (205: fn. 8)

At this point one wants to jump up and... On a more peaceful note, I 
cannot help but state that Seuren is just as "forgetful" or "careless" as 
he accuses Chomsky of being. Some such instances are:

- in section 2.2.1 on p. 34, one reads: "see section 2.2.1."
- the German for 'president' in sentence (29a) on p. 221 is misspelled 
- on p. 188, a section "4.1.1.1" is referred to, which doesn't exist 
(intended was one 4.1.1 less)

CONCLUSION

Do I have anything positive to say about Seuren's book? No, not really. 
Since it's rhetorically very hostile, it can hardly be called "balanced" 
and since it doesn't refer to any real literature or research, it can 
hardly be called "informed." These factors lead to only one conclusion: 
_Chomsky's Minimalism_ is just not informing.

Is it at least entertaining? If you like Chomsky-bashing, sure thing! 
(Then you'll surely find a warm welcome at all those websites and blogs 
dedicated to this type of activity and references to _The Anti-Chomsky 
Reader_ and other works -- one of which, Michael Covington's (at 
http://www.covingtoninnovations.com/michael/blog/0412), praises the book 
under review with the words: "It is all the more impressive if you've met 
Seuren (as I have) and realize that he is a very mild-mannered person." 
Well, big deal. I haven't met Seuren and I'm sorry, but I can't say that 
this is the style of "a very mild-mannered person.")

Does it provide new insights into the study and/or architecture of 
grammar, analysis, minimalism, and so on? My answer is a very simple "No."

I conclude that this book offers very little beyond heavy rhetoric and 
misunderstandings-turned-unjustified-criticism. Admittedly, this review 
was written by someone who is very biased against the kind of criticisms 
the author offers. That said, the author himself is very biased towards 
the program he set out to criticize. To get a different impression of the 
book and its virtues and possible shortcomings (or as I would put it, its 
shortcomings and possible virtues), one would need to read a review by 
someone as antagonistic to the Minimalist Program as Seuren, or someone 
who went "with Chomsky" a long way and split for whatever reason with the 
rise of the Minimalist Program. 

REFERENCES

Chomsky, Noam (1986) Knowledge of Language: Its Nature, Origin, and Use. 
New York: Praeger.

Chomsky, Noam (1995) The Minimalist Program. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Chomsky, Noam (1998) Linguagem e mente: Pensamentos atuais sobre antigos 
problemas [= Language and Mind: Current Thoughts on Ancient Problems, Part 
I and Part II. Lectures presented at the Universidade de Brasilia, 1996.]. 
Brasilia: Editora Universidade de Brasilia. [Seuren adds: "(Page 
references are to the English text as sent from MIT.)"]

Chomsky, Noam (2000a) New Horizons in the Study of Language and Mind. 
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Chomsky, Noam (2000b) 'Minimalist Inquiries: The Framework'. In R. Martin, 
M. Davis & J. Uriagereka, eds. Step by Step: Essays on Minimalist Syntax 
in Honor of Howard Lasnik. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 89-155.

Chomsky, Noam (2001) 'Derivation by Phase'. In M. Kenstowicz, ed. Ken 
Hale: A Life in Language. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1-52.

Chomsky, Noam (2002) On Nature and Language. Ed. by A. Belletti & L. 
Rizzi. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Chomsky, Noam (2004) 'Beyond Explanatory Adequacy'. In A. Belletti, ed. 
Structures and Beyond: The Cartography of Syntactic Structures, Vol. 3. 
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 104-131.

Chomsky, Noam (2005) 'On Phases'. Ms., MIT.

Cook, Vivian & Mark Newson (1996) Chomsky's Universal Grammar: An 
Introduction. Oxford: Blackwell.

Harris, Zellig S. (1951) Methods in Structural Linguistics. Chicago: The 
University of Chicago Press. [NB: Page references quoted above refer to 
the fourth imprint of 1964 published under the title _Structural 
Linguistics_.]

Hornstein, Norbert, Jairo Nunes, and Kleanthes K. Grohmann (in press) 
Understanding Minimalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 
[expected: September 2005]

Johnson, David E. & Shalom Lappin (1997) 'A Critique of the Minimalist 
Program'. Linguistics & Philosophy 20, 272-333.

Johnson, David E. & Shalom Lappin (1999) Local Constraints vs. Economy. 
Stanford, Calif.: CSLI Publications

Kayne, Richard. (1984) Connectedness and Binary Branching. Dordrecht: 
Foris.

Lakoff, George. (1971) 'On Generative Semantics'. In D. D. Steinberg and 
L. A. Jakobovits, eds. Semantics: An Interdisciplinary Reader in 
Philosophy, Linguistics and Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University 
Press, 232-296.

Lebeaux, David (1983) 'A Distributional Difference between Reciprocals and 
Reflexives'. Linguistic Inquiry 14, 723-730.

Lyons, John (1968) Introduction to Theoretical Linguistics. Cambridge: 
Cambridge University Press.

May, Robert. (1977) 'The Grammar of Quantification'. Ph.D. diss., MIT.

McCawley, James D. (1972) 'A Program for Logic'. In D. Davidson & G. 
Harman, eds. Semantics of Natural Language. Dordrecht: Reidel, 498-554.

Seuren, Pieter A. M. (1996) Semantic Syntax. Oxford: Blackwell.

Seuren, Pieter A. M. (1998) Western Linguistics: An Historical 
Introduction. Oxford: Blackwell.

Seuren, Pieter A. M. (2001) A View of Language. Oxford: Oxford University 
Press.

Wilder, Chris, Hans-Martin Gärtner & Manfred Bierwisch, eds. (1997) The 
Role of Economy Principles in Linguistic Theory. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

For discussion of the material reviewed and comments on this review, I am 
grateful to Winnie Lechner and Pieter Seuren, for encouragement and 
feedback, to Cedric Boeckx and Norbert Hornstein.] 

ABOUT THE REVIEWER

The reviewer is Assistant Professor of Theoretical Linguistics in the 
Department of English Studies at the University of Cyprus in Nicosia. His 
main interests lie in syntactic theory (esp. within Principles-and-
Parameters approaches) and comparative syntax (esp. Germanic, Romance, 
Slavic, Greek). He has worked on different topics, such as wh-
constructions, left dislocation and resumption, cliticization, and reverse 
locality effects, ("anti-locality"). He is also a member of the expert 
panel of the Ask-A-Linguist service offered by LINGUIST List. For further 
personal and professional information see 
www.punksinscience.org/kleanthes





-----------------------------------------------------------
LINGUIST List: Vol-16-1890	

	



More information about the LINGUIST mailing list