Here's Givon text: Dan Everett on Piraha and Universals
Suzanne Kemmer
kemmer at rice.edu
Mon Oct 1 21:08:05 UTC 2007
Dear Funknetters,
Funknet doesn't take email attachments (to avoid spreading viruses
and for other technical reasons),
so I got the following text from Tom and will disseminate it for
him. I am leaving the page breaks in,
in case people want to paste it back to a Word document.
--Suzanne
RE: DAN EVERETT ON PIRAHA AND UNIVERSALS
T. Givón
White Cloud Ranch
Ignacio,
Colorado
When Dan Everett came out with his original peer-review article
("Cultural constraints on grammar and cognition in Piraha" , Current
Anthropology 46.4, 2005), I was disappointed with the peer
reviewers' response (or lack thereof) to one major area where he
stakes his claims, so-called 'recursivity'. My disappointment
centered first on the fact that Dan, while going after Chomsky
(cf. Hauser, Chomsky & Fitch 2002) with the relish of a recent
convert, let Chomsky–once again, alas--dictate both the agenda and
terms of engagement. But I also thought that few of the peer
respondents did justice to the issues of syntactic complexity that
were either raised or implied in Dan's work. My disappointment
persisted through the eventual discussion earlier this year on
Funknet. So I thought it would perhaps be useful to raise the
topic once again, and if nothing else give both Dan and y'all a
second go at it.
1. Chomsky's 'recursivity' as a framework:
It is indeed sad to see the Hauser et al. (2002) article being
allowed to frame our discussion, indeed dictate its terms. That
article was one more attempt, undisguised, to resurrect 'competence'
as the bastion of pure innateness. This was presumably achieved by
singling out one important property of human grammar(s)--syntactic
complexity achieved through the embedding of clauses inside other
clauses--as the real essence of human grammar, and then claiming
that this unique property is not the product of adaptive-selective
evolution. There are a zillion issues wrapped up in this tortuous
intellectual exercise. First, there are many other major and minor
functional and structural properties of human grammar that are
just as species-unique--declarative speech acts, multi-propositional
coherence, referential displacement, multiple grammatical
morphologies and syntactic constructions (and their attendant
semantic-pragmatic correlates). Why single out 'recursivity'? Never
mind that recursive-hierarchic structure is actually the hallmark of
complex, automated biological processing in motor-control, memory,
vision and other complex behaviors, all predating homo sapiens by
healthy margins.
Next, by lumping up all complex/embedded constructions under the
rubric of 'recursivity', one tends to obscures the fact, well-
known from both child-language and diachronic-syntax research, that
different complex constructions arise in different communicative
contexts, under different adaptive pressures, at starkly different
ages in children (Diessel 2005), and through distinctly different
diachronic pathways of grammaticalization. By lumping them all
together into 'recursivity', and by insulating 'recursivity' from
both its adaptive (communicative) motivation and its developmental
(diachronic, ontogenetic) sources, one guts the issue of syntactic
complexity. All that is left is the abstract computational aspect
(Simon 1962).
2/everett.07
Further, Chomsky's Generative approach to universals has always been
distinctly Platonic and patently non-biological. Only properties of
language that are attested in 100% of human languages are universal.
A single 'exception' shoots down the rule. But neither biology nor
behavior nor language are amenable to this pristine view of
universals. They are notoriously subject to variation and
gradation, and those are in turn introduced and mediated by the
developmental processes that shape both structure and behavior--
evolution, ontogeny, diachrony. Indeed, in order to achieve his
pristine universals, Chomsky has found in necessary to make
universals more and more abstract and increasingly removed from the
visible phenomenology of language.
In one sense, however, Chomsky has had the right intuition about
universals: They are not the mere list of visible properties manifest
in extant (or extinct) languages. Rather, they are principles that
'govern'--or in our terms, explain--the visible phenomenology. And
they manifest their 'government' through the developmental
processes--acquisition and diachrony–in much the same way as
universals of biology manifest themselves through phylogeny
(evolution) and ontogeny (embryology). In both biology and language,
the reason why variation and 'exceptions' are both possible and
necessary is because the underlying adaptive principles are often in
conflict ('conflicting motivation'), and pull structures in
different directions, often in a see-saw fashion. Thus, in phonology,
articulation & perception are at constant loggerhead with each other.
And likewise in grammaticalization, similarity to related source
construction pulls in one direction (analogical extension and
synonymy), while communicative distinctness pulls in the other
(specialization and differentiation). But Chomsky, much like
Saussure, was not about to subject his principles and parameters to
the messy vagaries of acquisition and diachrony. The entire
Generative enterprise rests on this rejection of the relevance of
change and variation. This is where 'competence' rides in to the
rescue.
2. The diachrony of complex/embedded constructions
Embedded constructions in both the verb-phase and the noun-phrase
fall under the unified intonation contour of the host main-clause.
This is the most general structural feature of embedding.
Invariably, however, these syntactic constructions start their life
as paratactic ones--two clauses under separate intonation contours
but already performing the communicative function of embedded
clauses. The condensation--or merger--under a single intonation
contour is the earliest structural indication of the
grammaticalization of complex clauses (Mithun 2006, 2007). The
literature on this parataxis-to-syntaxis trend is massive, and some
of it not all that recent (Givón 1971, 1979; Dahl 2004; Heine and
Kouteva 2007; Givón 2006, 2007; inter alia). It involves a two-step
developmental trend:
(a) Parataxis to syntaxis
(b) Syntaxis to morphology/lexis
Each of those steps contributes to the rise of complex-hierarchic
structure--syntactic and lexical, respectively.
3/everett.07
Grammaticalization is multi-stepped and 'cyclical', the latter
meaning that it may move from the earliest 'source' stage to a
'mature' construction stage, and eventually to phonologically-
induced deterioration and back to zero. Most syntactic constructions
and morphologies grammaticalize independently of each other. Only in
post-pidgin contexts do constructions start together from zero. And
such seeming synchronicity is temporary. For each potentially-
complex syntactic construction (REL-clause, V-complement, passive,
cleft, WH-question, etc.), one can catch a language at any given
point of the developmental cycle. Piraha is not exactly unique in
showing an early paratactic stage of REL-clauses and V-complement.
Serial-verb languages all over Africa and Southeast Asia are in the
same typological bag. Bambara (Mendeic) and Supyire (Senufu) are
there. In both, however, the earliest step of clausal complexity--
merger of intonation contours--is already discernable, more advanced
in Bambara, less so in Supyire. The same is true of Hittite. The
same of Mohawk. The same in scores of Southeast Asian languages. All
you have to do is catch them at the early stage of the
grammaticalization cycle. But cycles--and their stages-- come and go,
often gradually, often piecemeal. Is it so unique to catch a language
at a particular stage?
3. Does culture constrain grammaticalization?
If the diachronic facts indeed hold, as I think they do, then the
question about the role of culture in constraining grammar must be
recast as 'the role of culture in constraining grammaticalization'.
Put another way: Is the fact that we find a language at an early
stage of the rise--most often renovation--of complex construction in
any way correlated to culture? The challenge for Everett here is
two-fold. First, of the languages that display, roughly, the same
early paratactic stage of the rise of complex clauses, some are small
hunting-and-gathering societies-of-intimates (Piraha), some are old-
establish pre-industrial cultivators with much larger social units
(Bambara, Supyire, Mohawk), some are agrarian city-states or even
empires (Hittite, Han Chinese). What exactly does culture predict here?
And second, grammatical constructions rise and fall. And their
renovation seems to be motivated largely by communicative need. In
most language where we have historical or reconstructive evidence,
one could show two or even three generations of rise-and-fall of the
same construction. And most often no cultural change is correlated
with such diachronic cycles. Did German revert to a society-of-
intimates ca. 300-400 years ago when it was renovating its REL-
clause construction, reverting to parataxis? And did it then sprint
back to the industrial revolution when it eventually proceeded to
well-grammaticalized syntaxis (merged intonation contours, de-
stressed REL-pronouns)? Did the ascendant Han empire change from an
intimate hunting-and-gathering society to a complex society-of-
strangers as it created, one piece at a time, the complex syntactic
construction of Mandarin Chinese--in every case starting from
parataxis of clause-chaining? And did Han culture collapse earlier
on, back to an intimate small society of hunters-and- gatherers,
when it expanded imperially, moved east and south, and took over the
vast Austro-Asiatic
4/everett.07
substratum--and in the process 'regressed' from the highly-complex
Bodic-Tibetan Syntax to the near-pidgin parataxis of the Tao The
Ching? Did the Hittite empire change culturally between the
paratactic REL-clause of Old Hittite and the embedded REL-clauses of
Middle Hittite?
If one advocates cultural constraints on grammaticalization, in this
case on the presence or absence of complex/embedded, one needs to
demonstrate some, hopefully consistent, correlations between cultural
and linguistic traits.
References
Dahl, O. (2004) The Growth and Maintenance of Linguistic
Complexity, Amsterdam: J. Benjamins
Diessel, H. (2005) The Acquisition of Complex Sentences,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Everett, D. (2005) "Cultural constraints on grammar and cognition in
Piraha", Current Anthropology, 46.4
Givón, T. (1971) "Historical syntax and synchronic morphology: An
archaeologist's field trip", CLS #7, Chicago: Chicago Linguistics
Society
Givón, T. (1979) On Understanding Grammar, NY: Academic Press
Givón, T. (2006) "Multiple routes to clause union: On the diachrony
of syntactic complexity", Seminario de Complexidad Sitáctica,
Universidad de Sonora, Hermosillo, November 2006 (ms)
Givón, T. (2007) "Toward a diachronic typology of relative clauses",
Symposium on the Genesis of Syntactic Complexity, Rice University,
Houston, March 2008 (ms)
Hauser, M., N. Chomsky and T. Fitch (2002) "The faculty of language:
What it is, what it has, and how it evolved", Science, 298
Heine, B. and T. Kouteva (2007) The Genesis of Grammar, Oxford:
Oxford University Press
Mithun, M. (2006) "Structural parameters of clause integration:
Complementation in Mohawk", Seminario de Complejidad Sintáctica,
Universidad de Sonora, Hermosillo (ms)
Mithun, M. (2007) "Threads in the tapestry of syntax: Complementation
and Mohawk", UC Santa Barbara (ms)
Simon, H. (1962) "The architecture of complexity", Proc. Amer.
Philos. Society, 106.6
More information about the Funknet
mailing list