Review of research on gesture
Sherman Wilcox
wilcox at unm.edu
Tue May 13 03:40:02 UTC 2014
Thanks for this wonderful post, Randy. It's a feast!
--
Sherman Wilcox, Ph.D.
Professor
Department of Linguistics
University of New Mexico
Humanities 112
400 Yale Blvd. NE
Albuquerque, NM 87131
USA
On 12 May 2014, at 19:47, Randy LaPolla wrote:
> As Karl Popper said (Unended Quest: An Intellectual Autobiography
> (1976), Page 29): "Always remember that it is impossible to speak in
> such a way that you cannot be misunderstood: there will always be some
> who misunderstand you." It seems several people took what I said in
> the wrong way.
>
> Although Popper didn't understand it, the reason why his observation
> is correct is that communication isn't based on coding and decoding of
> a shared code.
>
> To answer Johanna Rubba, communication happens when one person does
> something with the intention of another person guessing the reason for
> them doing it, and when the other person gets it right, you get
> communication. That is it, there is nothing more to communication.
>
> This view of communication argues that a basic mechanism for making
> sense of phenomena we experience in the world is abductive inference:
> we observe a phenomenon or event (possibly using inductive inference
> to first make a generalization about it), and then use abductive
> inference to posit a hypothesis to explain why the phenomenon is the
> way it is or why some event happened the way it did. This involves
> creating a context of interpretation, using available assumptions, in
> which the phenomenon or event “makes sense” to us. This sort of
> inference is non-demonstrative (non-deductive), so the conclusion is
> not necessarily true, but we generally assume our conclusion is true
> until persuaded otherwise by further evidence of some type. The
> particular context of interpretation created will depend on the
> assumptions available to the individual, and as each individual has
> had different life experiences, the assumptions available will differ
> with each individual, and so all meaning-creation (understanding) will
> be subjective. Abductive inference is seen as the major mechanism by
> which we make sense of the world, and so is what gave rise to
> religion, philosophy, and ultimately science (which added the step of
> testing the hypothesis to try to falsify it), as well as most of our
> every-day beliefs. It is seen as a survival technique, as
> understanding the reason for some phenomenon or event can lead to us
> better dealing with that phenomenon or event.
>
> One application of this survival instinct is inferring the intentions
> of other humans, which we do instinctively in order to survive,
> particularly if their action is out of the ordinary, such as walk
> towards us with a knife in their hand. Most of the time people don’t
> intend for us to infer their intentions, but there are times when
> someone does something with the intention of another person inferring
> their intention in doing it, and if the other person does infer the
> intention correctly, communication has happened. That is all there is
> to communication. Communication is seen not as a coding-decoding
> process, but as involving one person showing the intention to
> communicate, intending for the other person to infer their intention
> in doing the communicative act, and abductive inference, creating a
> context of interpretation in which the ostensive act makes sense. Even
> the recognition of the communicative act as a communicative act
> requires abductive inference. As the inferential process involved in
> communication is the same as the one we use in understanding the
> natural world, understanding communication gives us a way towards a
> general theory of meaning creation.
>
> Language is not seen as crucial for communication in this view, but
> when used, the role of language is to constrain the creation of the
> context of interpretation by eliminating certain assumptions that
> might otherwise be included in the context of interpretation. Language
> is seen not as an object, but as interactional behavior which
> conventionalizes at the societal level and habitualizes at the
> individual level (much the same as any other societal convention or
> personal habit). Language behavior conventionalizes as speakers
> repeatedly use the same forms over and over to constrain the
> hearer’s creation of the context of interpretation in particular
> ways. Each society of speakers will chose different aspects of meaning
> to consistently constrain the interpretation of, and they will do it
> to different degrees if they do it at all, and they will use different
> mechanisms to do so, so we can investigate the structure of languages
> from the point of view of these three aspects. And as constraining the
> interpretation with extra linguistic material requires extra effort on
> the part of the speakers, for them to do this it must be important to
> them that the hearer understand that aspect of the meaning better than
> other aspects, and so all conventionalized aspects of language use are
> seen to reflect aspects of the cognition of the particular speakers of
> the language at the time the form was conventionalized. Over time the
> original motivation for using the form can be lost, but out of habit
> and convention the form will often continue to be used, and so will
> seem unmotivated (arbitrary), but it would not have conventionalized
> initially had it not been important to constrain that particular
> aspect of the interpretation at the time it conventionalized. Each
> language then is seen as uniquely reflecting the cognition of a
> particular society of speakers. This cognition involves construing and
> even perceiving the world differently in each language.
>
> This discussion has focused on language and gesture, but as Wally
> said, there are other aspects, such as prosody, that are equally
> relevant. Gumperz talked about many of these things as
> "contextualization cues". For me, all of what we do in a communicative
> situation can be a contextualization cue (I don't see a distinction
> between conceptual information and contextualization cues the way
> Gumperz did, or between conceptual and procedural information the way
> Relevance Theory does: everything helps in the creation of the context
> of interpretation). As Nick says, you have to take the whole
> communicative situation into account and see all aspects as working
> together towards the same goal, whether it involves "language" or
> "gesture" or "prosody" or whatever. Also, communication doesn't
> necessarily involve language or gesture or prosody. It can be leaving
> an item out in a conspicuous place, as when my part-time cook left out
> the almost-empty container of rice in order to communicate that I
> needed to buy more rice, or another time when she left a cup in the
> sink to communicate that the faucet was leaking and so I should have
> it fixed. Anything can be used in communication. We most often combine
> all of these elements together. If whatever we did to communicate
> worked, we will use it again when the same or similar situation
> arises, and then that can become a personal habit and a societal
> convention. This includes conventionalization of conversational
> routines, and also of gestures, as well as linguistic forms. All forms
> and conventions used in the communicative act have the same function:
> they constrain the creation of the context of inference of the
> addressee, that is, constrain the addressee's search for the relevance
> of the communicator's action. This is possible because of the
> Cooperative Principle, which at its core is really saying we assume
> people are rational, and so when they do something there must be a
> reason, and we can guess (using abductive inference) what that reason
> is, and thereby infer the person's communicative intent. Communication
> is never fully deterministic, as Popper points out, but by
> constraining the interpretation to a more appropriate extent (for the
> situation) you can be more likely to have the person infer what you
> intend for the person to infer.
>
> This is a very brief summary of a theory of language development and
> communication that I have developed over the last 20 years out of the
> intersection of my work in documenting languages radically different
> from IE languages, in historical linguistics, in typology, and in
> pragmatics. I teach a whole semester course on this. I recorded the
> class this past semester, and have begun putting the audio of the
> lectures and the slides on iTunes U
> (https://itunes.apple.com/us/course/pragmatics/id849441717 ). The
> first four or so hours go into great detail about how this works, with
> many natural examples, to show how abduction works and how it isn't
> coding and decoding and how anything can be communicative and how
> meaning creation generally works. (Somehow my assistant put them up in
> a way that the numbering is reversed, so start with item 17 ad work
> up, or just hit the sort button to reverse the sort. The slides to go
> with the audio are called "Notes" on the site.) The course is
> officially called Pragmatic Theory, but for me it is Meaning Creation,
> as it is all about how we create meaning in our minds (the only place
> where meaning is--there is no meaning in letters or sounds, any
> meaning we "get" is created in our minds based on our experiences).
>
> I also have some papers presenting the theory, and some also applying
> the theory to things like the nature of grammatical relations:
>
> LaPolla, Randy J. 1997. "Grammaticalization as the fossilization of
> constraints on interpretation: Towards a single theory of cognition,
> communication, and the development of language". Paper presented to
> the City University of Hong Kong Seminar in Linguistics, November 6,
> 1997.
>
> http://tibeto-burman.net/rjlapolla/papers/LaPolla-1997-Grammaticalization_as_the_Fossilization_of_Constraints_on_Interpretation.pdf
>
>
>
> LaPolla, Randy J. 2003. Why languages differ: Variation in the
> conventionalization of constraints on inference. In David Bradley,
> Randy J. LaPolla, Boyd Michailovsky & Graham Thurgood (eds.), Language
> variation: Papers on variation and change in the Sinosphere and in the
> Indosphere in honour of James A. Matisoff, 113-144. Canberra: Pacific
> Linguistics.
>
> http://tibeto-burman.net/rjlapolla/papers/LaPolla_2003_Why_languages_differ_-_Variation_in_the_conventionalization_of_constraints_on_inference.pdf
>
>
>
> LaPolla, Randy J. 2005. Typology and complexity. In James W. Minett
> and William S-Y. Wang (eds.), Language acquisition, change and
> emergence: Essays in evolutionary linguistics, 465-493. Hong Kong:
> City University of Hong Kong Press.
>
> http://tibeto-burman.net/rjlapolla/papers/LaPolla_2005_Typology_and_Complexity.PDF
>
>
>
> LaPolla, Randy J. 2006. On grammatical relations as constraints on
> referent identification. In Tasaku Tsunoda and Taro Kageyama (eds.),
> Voice and grammatical relations: Festschrift for Masayoshi Shibatani
> (Typological Studies in Language), 139-151. Amsterdam & Philadelphia:
> John Benjamins Pub. Co.
>
> http://tibeto-burman.net/rjlapolla/papers/LaPolla_2006_On_Grammatical_Relations_as_Constraints_on_Referent_Identification.pdf
>
>
>
> LaPolla, Randy J. 2006. The how and why of syntactic relations.
> Invited plenary address and keynote of the Centre for Research on
> Language Change Workshop on Grammatical Change at the Annual
> Conference of the Australian Linguistics Society, University of
> Queensland, 7-9 July, 2006. To appear in Christian Lehmann, Stavros
> Skopeteas, Christian Marschke (eds.), Evolution of syntactic relations
> (Trends in Linguistics Series). Berlin: Mouton De Gruyter.
>
> http://tibeto-burman.net/rjlapolla/papers/LaPolla_Draft_The_how_and_why_of_syntactic_relations.pdf
>
>
>
> LaPolla, R. J. 2010. “On the logical necessity of a cultural
> connection for all aspects of linguistic structure”. Paper presented
> at the 10th RCLT International Workshop, “The Shaping of Language:
> The Relationship between the Structures of Languages and their Social,
> Cultural, Historical, and Natural Environments”, 14 July 2010.
>
> https://www.dropbox.com/s/zijgwtkkr0qtadq/LaPolla-2010-On_the_Logical_Necessity_of_a_Cultural_Connection_for_All_Aspects_of_Linguistic_Structure.pdf
>
>
> Randy
> -----
> Prof. Randy J. LaPolla, PhD FAHA (罗仁地)| Head, Division of
> Linguistics and Multilingual Studies | Nanyang Technological
> University
> HSS-03-80, 14 Nanyang Drive, Singapore 637332 | Tel: (65) 6592-1825
> GMT+8h | Fax: (65) 6795-6525 | http://randylapolla.net/
>
> On May 12, 2014, at 3:57 PM, Tahir Wood wrote:
>
>>>>> Johanna Rubba <jrubba at calpoly.edu> 2014/05/09 06:50 PM >>>
>> Fundamentally, if language (as opposed to gesture) isn't at all
>> necessary to communication, why did it evolve? It is a pretty
>> elaborate system to have evolved in the absence of a need for it.
>>
>> There is another view regarding evolution, and that is that language
>> emerged first as a mute system of inner modeling (Sebeok et al) and
>> only later "exapted" for communication. Obviously language would have
>> made a huge difference in the potentials for communication, which
>> itself would have reflected back into enhanced thought processes
>> again. Explaining it this way does have the merit of avoiding the
>> mechanistic view, in which humans initially had thoughts just as we
>> do and so they developed language "in order to express" those
>> thoughts (!)
>> Tahir
>
> On May 10, 2014, at 12:50 AM, Johanna Rubba wrote:
>
>>
>> Language "not at all necessary for communication"? I'd like to ask
>> Randy to define communication. Certainly language isn't the only form
>> of communication, but I can't imagine how people would build a
>> society without being able to communicate about abstractions,
>> hypotheticals, inner thoughts and feelings, the past, and the future.
>> I guess it would be helpful also for Randy to define gesture. He says
>> that it isn't sign language, and indeed that it isn't language. But I
>> don't know of any non-language communication system that deals with
>> abstractions, which are certainly essential to human culture. And,
>> although media like phones and writing lack gesture, communication
>> can still happen through them, albeit incomplete.
>>
>> Fundamentally, if language (as opposed to gesture) isn't at all
>> necessary to communication, why did it evolve? It is a pretty
>> elaborate system to have evolved in the absence of a need for it.
>>
>> Dr. Johanna Rubba, Professor, Linguistics
>> Linguistics Minor Advisor
>> English Department
>> Cal Poly State University, San Luis Obispo
>> Tel. 805.756.2184
>> Dept. Tel 805.756.2596
>> E-mail: jrubba at calpoly.edu
>> URL: http://cla.calpoly.edu/~jrubba
>> *******************************************
>> "Justice is what love looks like in public."
>> - Cornel West
More information about the Funknet
mailing list