22.31, Review: Anthropological Ling; Cognitive Science: Larson et al. (2010)

linguist at LINGUISTLIST.ORG linguist at LINGUISTLIST.ORG
Tue Jan 4 23:24:04 UTC 2011


LINGUIST List: Vol-22-31. Tue Jan 04 2011. ISSN: 1068 - 4875.

Subject: 22.31, Review: Anthropological Ling; Cognitive Science: Larson et al. (2010)

Moderators: Anthony Aristar, Eastern Michigan U <aristar at linguistlist.org>
            Helen Aristar-Dry, Eastern Michigan U <hdry at linguistlist.org>
 
Reviews: Monica Macaulay, U of Wisconsin-Madison  
Eric Raimy, U of Wisconsin-Madison  
Joseph Salmons, U of Wisconsin-Madison  
Anja Wanner, U of Wisconsin-Madison  
       <reviews at linguistlist.org> 

Homepage: http://linguistlist.org/

The LINGUIST List is funded by Eastern Michigan University, 
and donations from subscribers and publishers.

Editor for this issue: Monica Macaulay <monica at linguistlist.org>
================================================================  

This LINGUIST List issue is a review of a book published by one of our
supporting publishers, commissioned by our book review editorial staff. We
welcome discussion of this book review on the list, and particularly invite
the author(s) or editor(s) of this book to join in. If you are interested in 
reviewing a book for LINGUIST, look for the most recent posting with the subject 
"Reviews: AVAILABLE FOR REVIEW", and follow the instructions at the top of the 
message. You can also contact the book review staff directly.

===========================Directory==============================  

1)
Date: 04-Jan-2011
From: Karl Diller [karl.diller at unh.edu]
Subject: The Evolution of Human Language
 

	
-------------------------Message 1 ---------------------------------- 
Date: Tue, 04 Jan 2011 18:22:36
From: Karl Diller [karl.diller at unh.edu]
Subject: The Evolution of Human Language

E-mail this message to a friend:
http://linguistlist.org/issues/emailmessage/verification.cfm?iss=22-31.html&submissionid=3797918&topicid=9&msgnumber=1
 
Discuss this message: 
http://linguistlist.org/pubs/reviews/get-review.cfm?subid=3797918

 


Announced at http://linguistlist.org/issues/21/21-328.html 

EDITORS:  Richard K Larson, Viviane Déprez, Hiroko Yamakido
TITLE:  The Evolution of Human Language
SUBTITLE:  Biolinguistic Perspectives
PUBLISHER:  Cambridge University Press
YEAR:  2010

Karl Diller, Cann Lab (genetics), University of Hawaii at Manoa, and Linguistics
program (Emeritus professor), University of New Hampshire

SUMMARY

This book is an outgrowth of a 2005 symposium at Stony Brook in which the intent
was to explore the implications of Hauser, Chomsky, and Fitch's paper ''The
Faculty of Language: What Is It, Who Has It, and How Did It Evolve?'' (2002).
That paper, hereafter 'HCF,' is reprinted as chapter 1. Then 14 chapters,
including additional chapters by Hauser, Chomsky, and Fitch on their own,
respond to issues raised by the original paper. 

The basic intent of HCF and of this book is to explore how or whether generative
linguistics can be reconciled with biological evolution. If it has been hard to
fit generative grammar into evolutionary theory, it is because of the focus on
the language of an ideal speaker-hearer, I-Language, in an idealized homogeneous
speech community, specifically ruling out an evolutionary setting. The editors
argue that in the principles and parameters model, ''the linguistics 'module' was
unique in content among all our faculties... [and] the question of language origins
could gain no empirical or theoretical traction'' (p. 3). In moving from the
principles and parameters model to the minimalist model, they argue, generative
grammar has opened itself to these questions of origin in an evolutionary setting. 

The editors state that nearly all of the authors have been ''influenced in one
way or another by the Hauser, Chomsky, and Fitch (HCF) paper'' (p. 1), but
nevertheless the majority of chapters dispute various arguments of the HCF
paper, such as whether 'recursion' is important for the origin of language,
whether or not language is basically for thought or for communication, and
whether natural selection and adaptation apply to the origin of language. There
is enough difference in approach to provide some interesting and good scientific
dialog.

The original Hauser, Chomsky and Fitch paper is well known for its distinction
between the broad sense 'faculty of language' (FLB) and the narrow sense
'faculty of language' (FLN). FLN is ''the abstract linguistic computation system
alone'' (p. 17), reduced in minimalist theory to the operation 'merge' which
embodies recursion. FLB includes the 'sensory-motor' and
'conceptual-intentional' systems, which are linked together by the FLN. The
peripheral parts of FLB are said to ''have an ancient evolutionary history, long
predating the emergence of language'' (p. 23), whereas FLN is uniquely human.
Human uniqueness is ''an overarching concern'' for HCF (p. 21), in contrast to the
search for connections and the continuity of life in evolutionary thought. They
argue that the narrowness and uniqueness of the FLN renders ''the status of FLN
as an adaptation open to question'' (p. 23). The suggestion is made that even
recursion evolved as a 'spandrel,' for some reason other than language -- for
navigation, perhaps, for example.

Chomsky follows up these ideas in chapter 2, ''Some simple evo-devo theses: how
true might they be for language?'' Starting off with the statement that ''Study of
evolution of some system is feasible only to the extent that its nature is
understood'' (p. 45), two thirds of the chapter are devoted to understanding
language in terms of principle and parameters theory and minimalist theory. The
upshot is that ''Evolution in the biological sense of the term would then be
restricted to the mutation that yielded the operation Merge...'' (p. 61) which
would enable ''capacities for complex thought, planning, interpretation, and so
on'' (p. 59), but not would not, at first, involve communication.
'Externalization' (i.e. speech, sign language, lexicalization, communication,
etc.) came later and ''may not have involved an evolutionary change -- that is,
genomic change'' (p. 61). Accordingly, he argues, ''any approach to evolution of
language that focuses on communication, or the SM [sensory-motor] system, or
statistical properties of spoken language, and the like, may well be seriously
misguided'' (p. 61). Chomsky envisions the sudden emergence of human language
rather recently in the history of the human species, which, he says, ''would lead
one to expect something more like a snowflake than the outcome of extensive
Jacobian 'tinkering' over a long period'' (p. 59). Chomsky argues that the neural
change for Merge, using Tattersall's words, ''probably had nothing to do with
adaptation,'' and that ''the appearance of language and its anatomical correlates
was not driven by natural selection'' (p. 59).  Since adaptation and natural
selection are key to the biologist's view of evolution, Chomsky's view of
biological evolution is indeed minimal, when it comes to language.

''Your theory of language evolution depends on your theory of language'' is Ray
Jackendoff's argument in chapter 3. Acknowledging the wider context of various
theories of language resulting in different notions of what, if anything, is
innate and special for language, Jackendoff contrasts his own theory of a
parallel architecture for syntax and semantics with Chomsky's syntactocentric
architecture of language. He gives a persuasive example of recursion in the
visual system to show that recursion is not special to language (p. 69). The
parallel architecture is much more compatible with the biologist's view of
evolution. As he says, ''with the parallel architecture, one can imagine various
scenarios in which the language capacity evolves in stages, each adding an
increment to the system's communicative efficiency and flexibility...'' There is a
fair amount special to humans, ''but it is motivated by its incremental
adaptability'' (p. 71).

Since 'recursion' is central to the HCF paper, Tecumseh Fitch attempts to
clarify the concept by discussing ''Three meanings of 'recursion': key
distinctions for biolinguistics'' in chapter 4 -- usages from computer science,
linguistics, and meta-mathematics.

In chapter 5, ''On obfuscation, obscurantism, and opacity: evolving conceptions
of the faculty of language,'' Marc Hauser expresses his ''frustration'' at the
critiques of the HCF paper, suggesting a ''wanton eagerness to misunderstand,
misconstrue, or fabricate'' among the critics, or worse that ''the study of
language evolution is doomed to endless obfuscation, obscurantism, and opacity!''
(p. 91). He then defends the HCF paper point by point. He concludes, ''I hope
these clarifications help. If not, let me know and I will return to the pub for
consolation'' (p. 99).

Three chapters in part two of this book, ''Language and the interface systems,''
extend well beyond the concerns of the narrow sense faculty of language. Peter
Gärdenfors and Mathias Osvath discuss ''Prospection as a cognitive precursor to
symbolic communication,'' arguing that the ''Oldowan culture, 2.6 -- 1.5 million
years ago, constituted an ecological niche containing evolutionary forces that
generated symbolic cognition. The long-ranging character of this culture made
the use of prospective cognition, that is the skill to plan for future events
and needs, beneficial'' (p. 104).  An important result of their argument is that
''Coherent with evolutionary theory, this suggests that there was a gradual shift
into symbolic cognition, in contrast to explanations relying on discontinuity''
(p. 114).

Michael Corballis argues in chapter 7 that language evolved before speech.
Chimpanzees and other apes cannot be taught to mimic human speech, but they can
be taught to communicate to a certain extent with sign language and other visual
sign systems. Humans, then, were pre-adapted for a visual language. He argues
that a gradual evolution from manual sign to speech could overcome what Robin
Burlings has called the ''nearly fatal flaw'' (p. 119) of the gestural theory, of
why one would switch from a perfectly adequate manual-visual language to an
audible one, if mimicry and speech were nearly impossible for chimpanzees.

Dan Sperber and Gloria Origgi give ''A pragmatic perspective on the evolution of
language'' in chapter 8. They contrast the ''code model'' of communication with an
''inferential model'' which goes well beyond the code to interpret the meaning of
an utterance in context. They argue that the inferential model is necessary for
a structured code to develop -- and for the code to change rapidly as it does in
human language. The inferential model allows communication to precede grammar.

Part three of the book, ''Biological and Neurological Foundations,'' starts off
with a discussion by Daniel Dor and Eva Jablonka of ''Plasticity and canalization
in the evolution of linguistic communication: an evolutionary developmental
approach.'' Plasticity is the ability of an organism or the brain to change in
response to different environmental circumstances; canalization is the tendency
to keep stable in the face of different environmental stimuli. They envision a
co-evolutionary spiral which for the evolution of language is ''first and
foremost a socially driven process.'' They say that ''Language not only adapted to
the brains and minds of individual speakers, but the brains and minds of the
speakers had to adapt themselves to language'' (p. 147).

Massimo Piatelli-Palmarini brings us back in chapter 10 to the generative
viewpoint that ''I-languages are what one has to attempt to reconstruct the
evolution of, when dealing with language evolution'' (p. 150).  He argues that
''the evolution of language may not be the result of a cumulation of a host of
smaller steps...'' and that ''communication may not have been AT ALL the driving
force behind language'' (p. 161). He argues that ''Every inquiry into the
evolution of language must be an inquiry into the evolution of the computational
brain machinery capable of carrying out [the 'recursive handling' of]
edge-features operations'' (p. 151).

Philip Lieberman's chapter (11) is titled ''The creative capacity of language, in
what manner is it unique, and who had it?'' The focus, however, is on the neural
and anatomical structures that underlie language and speech. The recursive
properties of language he subsumes under ''reiteration'' which is mediated by
sub-cortical structures. Reiteration for motor control (which extends to
dancing) is the basis for reiteration in language. For speech, he argues that
the length of the neck is a proxy for whether or not early humans had a modern
supralaryngeal vocal tract enabling speech as we know it, where the horizontal
and vertical parts of the vocal tract are about equal. He states that ''Speech,
language, and some degree of cognitive flexibility surely were present earlier,''
but that the long neck evidence for the fully modern supralaryngeal vocal tract
doesn't appear until some 50,000 years ago. The evidence is not yet published.

Studies comparing the language abilities of monozygotic and dizygotic twins are
the focus of Karin Stromswold's chapter 12, ''Genetics and the evolution of
language: what genetic studies reveal about the evolution of language.'' About
two thirds of language disorders are said to be due to genetics, as opposed to
environment, where language disorders are scored in such a way that one either
has or doesn't have the disorder. For normal language variation, the
methodological problems are more complex, and one finds genetic overlap with
various non-linguistic abilities. Her conclusion is that ''results of genetic
studies are most consistent with linguistic models and evolutionary theories
that invoke both general and language-specific factors... [but] they cannot tell us
the process by which language evolved'' (p. 190).

Part four of the book presents the Anthropological Context.  Ian Tattersall
focuses on ''behaviorally modern Homo sapiens'' in his chapter on ''A putative role
for language in the origin of human consciousness.'' He argues that although
anatomically modern humans appeared some 200,000 years ago, modern behavior
appears from about 50,000 years ago epitomized by the cave paintings and bone
flutes of the Cro Magnon in Europe and the systematic elimination of other
primate species of Homo.  The argument is that ''The most plausible candidate for
this cultural stimulus is the invention of language, an activity that is
virtually synonymous with our symbolic reasoning ability'' (p. 197). Arguing
against the linear and gradual model of the mid-twentieth century ''Evolutionary
Synthesis,'' he says that ''in evolution form has to precede function, if only
because without form there can be no function. Indeed ... any novelty must arise as
an ''exaption,'' a new variant arising independently of any novel function for
which it might be co-opted'' (p. 197). His conclusion is that ''Remarkable as our
species Homo sapiens undoubtedly is, it was not fine-tuned by evolution for
symbolic cognition and language'' (p. 198).

The strongest critique of Hauser, Chomsky and Fitch's view of language evolution
comes in Derek Bickerton's chapter, ''On two incompatible theories of language
evolution.'' Bickerton argues that HCF is ''a model so abstract that any account
of language evolution in terms of process is ruled out. That argument makes
sense only if the emergence of language is *not* a process, but an instantaneous
event'' (p. 200). Bickerton proposes an alternative: a process starting with a
protolanguage characterized by ''Sequence'' as opposed to ''Merge'' in which words
could have been linked together like ''beads on a string'' without grammar. His
scenario imagines an environmental pressure for a ''communicative system capable
of displacement,'' as in the system of bees and ants for recruitment to exploit
distant but rich food resources. Then ''Once established, protolanguage itself
became a selective pressure for its own expansion, and for mechanisms that would
then regularize, and thus automate and disambiguate, ever-lengthening
propositions -- mechanisms such as hierarchical structure and recursion. At the
beginning of the process, human ancestors had only a standard primate conceptual
system, but this co-evolved with language to gradually create the rich and
complex system that characterizes language today'' (p. 210).

In the final chapter, ''On the evolution of language: implications of a new and
general theory of human origins, properties, and history,'' Paul Bingham rejects
the idea that a mutation for merge or recursion was necessary: ''there is no
reason whatever to suppose that any qualitatively new neural/cognitive
capability was necessary to initiate the evolution of human language (or
communication more generally)'' (p. 223).  The evolution of language is put
squarely into the context of biological adaptations: ''language is merely one
element of a more complex 'total package' of adaptations for uniquely human
elite information exchange'' (p. 222). This generously wide adaptational context
is shrunk back, however, to a narrow rate-limiting step in the evolution of
language, ''the management of the conflict of interest problem'' in the context of
selfish genes and selfish animals (p. 223). Lower animals, he argues, could not
evolve wide circles of cooperation with non-kin because free riders always did
better in the short run. The problem is to impose a cost on free riding that
exceeds the benefit. In a kind of 'War is Peace' scenario, he argues that ''there
is only a single viable way to impose such costs on a free rider -- to inflict
violence'' (p. 217). The key, he argues, is the elite ability to throw stones
accurately so that the cooperators can ostracize the free rider with violence
from a distance, with relatively little danger to themselves. He argues that
evidence for elite throwing is present in late pre-human australopiths, followed
quickly by uniquely human social cooperation and 2 million years of brain
expansion. We might be wary, though, of the exclusiveness of Bingham's argument:
that for the evolution of language, the conflict of interest is ''the *sole*
limitation'' on the exchange of information; that ''NO OTHER FACTOR than solution
of the conflict of interest problem and NO NEW CAPABILITY  (ability to generate
and comprehend 'combinatorial symbolism' or a new level of individual
intelligence, for example) need precede evolution of elite, symbolic
communication ... which will evolve WITHOUT THE NECESSITY OF ANY OTHER
PRE-CONDITION'' (pp. 215-216, EMPHASIS his).

EVALUATION

The chief flaw of this book is its narrowness of scope. The editors express the
breathtakingly provincial opinion that ''HCF and related efforts have signaled a
symbolic lifting of the ban on investigations into the origin of language
officially imposed by the Linguistics Society of Paris in 1871 (p. 1).'' This
seems to overlook a great deal of work on the origin of language, including
important attempts even within the generative linguistics framework to reconcile
generative linguistics and biological evolution such as Pinker and Bloom (1990),
twenty years ago, and Lenneberg (1960), early on in the generative enterprise.
Likewise there is almost no acknowledgement of such processes as
grammaticalization and of the many varieties of cognitive and functional
linguistics that have had no disconnect with evolutionary theory. There is
little acknowledgement of the 150 years of interaction between neurolinguistics
and evolutionary theory, going back to the correspondence between Charles Darwin
and Paul Broca in the early 1860s.

It should be noted in passing, that the Paris ban on discussions of the origin
of language had an ideological anti-scientific motivation. The date was actually
1866, not 1871, and the ban was one of the original bylaws of the Société de
Linguistique de Paris (SLP). As we see on the SLP website, the SLP was founded
originally to support catholic and monarchist ideas and to counteract positivist
thinking. Specifically it was organized in order to oppose the Société
d'Anthropologie de Paris which had been founded by Broca in 1859
(http://www.slp-paris.com/index.html). Ten years later, in 1876, the Linguistic
Society of Paris was reconstituted on a less ideological basis as a learned
society with a new set of bylaws. The original bylaw banning discussion of the
origin of language cannot be taken seriously.

The most important question raised in this book is whether language (involving
maybe a mutation for 'merge') emerged recently with ''behaviorally modern
humans,'' long after the emergence of anatomically modern Homo sapiens, or
whether language coevolved with the changes seen in brain anatomy in the 2.5
million years since the pre-human australopithicines. Arguing for the recent
scenario, Tattersall talks of the ''invention'' of language. Does this imply that
language was simply a cultural phenomenon, not a biological one? The HCF paper
argues that natural selection and adaptation were not relevant to the evolution
of language. Does that imply that the biological basis of language was not
shaped specifically for language? The majority of chapters prefer a long term
evolutionary scenario with full language present at the emergence of
anatomically modern humans. The notion of a cultural revolution 50,000 years ago
when humans became ''behaviorally modern'' has been convincingly refuted by the
archeological evidence presented by McBrearty and Brooks (2000). The genetic
evidence likewise does not support the recent date (Diller and Cann 2009).
Modern humans had dispersed to all corners of Africa and into the Middle East by
100,000 years ago, to South Asia before the Toba volcanic eruption 74,000 years
ago, and to Australia perhaps by 60,000 years ago. Once the human population had
dispersed into widely isolated subgroups, chances were minimal for a mutation
for 'merge' spreading universally to everyone.

A second major question is whether language emerged for thought with
communication added on later, or whether it evolved as a system of communication
from the start. The majority of chapters see language as an evolved system for
communication.

A third question is the special status of 'recursion' in language. This is
clearly controversial: Jackendoff shows evidence of recursion in visual
thinking, and others see recursive processes as basic to mammalian cognition.

The majority of chapters do not accept Chomsky's argument that the broadly
construed faculty of language was not subject to biological evolution, and that
''Evolution in the biological sense of the term would then be restricted to the
mutation that yielded the operation Merge...'' (p. 61). Thus even without critiques
from the many varieties of cognitive and functional linguistics, the Hauser,
Chomsky and Fitch article does not fare well. 

Chomsky envisions the emergence of a neural change for 'merge' that is sudden
and perfect, ''more like a snowflake than the outcome of extensive Jacobian
'tinkering' over a long period'' (p. 59).  There is a phrase from Chomsky's 1959
review of Skinner's 'Verbal Behavior' that may be appropriate here: the
speculation about this magical mutation for 'merge' late in the history of Homo
sapiens may be just ''a kind of play-acting at science'' (Chomsky 1959: 39 ).

REFERENCES

Chomsky, Noam (1959). A review of B. F. Skinner's 'Verbal Behavior' (New York:
Appleton-Centuray-Crofts Inc, 1957) in Language, 35:1, 26-58. Reprinted in Fodor
and Katz (1964).

Diller, Karl C. and Rebecca L Cann (2009). Evidence against a genetic-based
revolution in language 50,000 years ago. In Rudolf Botha and Chris Knight, eds.,
The Cradle of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Fodor, Jerry A., and Jerrold J. Katz, eds., (1964). The Structure of Language:
Readings in the Philosophy of Language. Cambridge: MIT Press.

Hauser, Marc D., Noam Chomsky, and W. Tecumseh Fitch (2002). The Faculty of
Language: What is it, Who has it, and How did it Evolve? Science 298 (22
November 2002), 1569-1579.

Lenneberg, Eric H (1960). Language, Evolution, and Purposive Behavior. In S.
Diamond, ed., Culture in History: Essays in Honor of Paul Radin (New York:
Columbia University Press); Revised and extended version published as The
Capacity for Language Acquisition, in Jerry A Fodor and Jerrold J Katz, eds.
(1964). 

McBrearty, Sally, and Alison S. Brooks (2000). The revolution that wasn't: a new
interpretation of the origin of modern human behavior. Journal of Human
Evolution 39:5, 453-563.

Pinker, Steven, and Paul Bloom (1990). Natural language and natural selection.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13:4, 707-784.

ABOUT THE REVIEWER 

Karl Diller is currently working on the evolutionary genetics of language
in the Cann Lab (genetics) in the PhD program in Biomedical Science (Cell
and Molecular Biology), John A. Burns School of Medicine, University of
Hawaii at Manoa, Honolulu HI. He has a PhD in Linguistics from Harvard
University, and is professor emeritus of linguistics at the University of
New Hampshire. 




-----------------------------------------------------------
LINGUIST List: Vol-22-31	
----------------------------------------------------------


	



More information about the LINGUIST mailing list