14.3050, Review: Philosophy of Lang/Semantics: Woods (2003)

LINGUIST List linguist at linguistlist.org
Sun Nov 9 06:22:23 UTC 2003


LINGUIST List:  Vol-14-3050. Sun Nov 9 2003. ISSN: 1068-4875.

Subject: 14.3050, Review: Philosophy of Lang/Semantics: Woods (2003)

Moderators: Anthony Aristar, Wayne State U.<aristar at linguistlist.org>
            Helen Dry, Eastern Michigan U. <hdry at linguistlist.org>

Reviews (reviews at linguistlist.org):
	Sheila Collberg, U. of Arizona
	Terence Langendoen, U. of Arizona

Home Page:  http://linguistlist.org/

The LINGUIST List is funded by Eastern Michigan University, Wayne
State University, and donations from subscribers and publishers.

Editor for this issue: Naomi Ogasawara <naomi at linguistlist.org>
 ==========================================================================
What follows is a review or discussion note contributed to our Book
Discussion Forum.  We expect discussions to be informal and
interactive; and the author of the book discussed is cordially invited
to join in.

If you are interested in leading a book discussion, look for books
announced on LINGUIST as "available for review." Then contact
Simin Karimi at simin at linguistlist.org.



=================================Directory=================================

1)
Date:  Sat, 08 Nov 2003 23:32:40 +0000
From:  Leonor Santos <leonor at globalite.com.br>
Subject:  Conditionals

-------------------------------- Message 1 -------------------------------

Date:  Sat, 08 Nov 2003 23:32:40 +0000
From:  Leonor Santos <leonor at globalite.com.br>
Subject:  Conditionals

Woods, Michael (2003) Conditionals, Oxford University Press.

Announced at http://linguistlist.org/issues/14/14-1764.html


Maria Leonor Santos, Universidade Federal da Paraíba/ Universidade
Federal de Santa Catarina.

Synopsis of the book

Michael Woods' Conditionals should have been part of a more
comprehensive book on Philosophical Logic, that was left incomplete.
The author died in April 1993, and his Brasenose colleague John Foster
is responsible for the transcription, ordering and editing of the
material left.  The object of this review is the first paperback
edition of Conditionals (2003).

The present book contains the Editor's Preface, by David Wiggins, 8
Chapters on conditionals, by Michael Woods, a Commentary by Dorothy
Edgington, a List of Works Cited, an Obituary by John Ackrill,
followed by Michael Woods Curriculum Vitae and the Index.

Conditionals are, as Editor David Wiggins says in his Preface to this
book, ''one of the oldest, most troublesome questions in logic''.  As
it is widely known, it is quite common for us to find problems when
trying to accommodate the description of natural language connectives
to their (presumed) corresponding formal connectives.  Natural
language connectives do not usually behave exactly the way the formal
connectives do, as it is easy to see when we contrast uses of ''and'',
''or'', and ''not'', on the one hand, with predicate calculus formulae
containing formal conjunction, disjunction and negation, on the other.
Conditionals, however, beat them all, and present a sort of acute case
of discrepancy.

Chapter One (The Varieties of Conditionals) presents the problem and
introduces the two types of conditionals, as they are usually known:
the so called indicative conditionals, on the one hand, and the
subjunctive, or counterfactual conditionals, on the other.  The first
problem with conditionals is that they seem to be a form of sentence
composition, but it is very difficult to determine whether the form is
a truth-functional one, and if so, what function gives us the
truth-value of the complete sentence, from the truth-values of the
component sentences.  Besides, conditionals come in assertions, but
also in questions and commands (a fact that is not always taken into
consideration in other treatments of the subject).  Non- assertoric
conditionals are postponed to Chapter Seven.  Woods also discusses the
inadequacy of the terms ''subjunctive'' and ''counterfactual'' for
conditionals, and the widespread characterization of the
counterfactual as one that implies the falsity of the antecedent.  He
surveys briefly some of the solutions found in the literature to the
question of assertibility of conditionals, and introduces his own
taxonomy: those conditionals that are made up of two stand-alone
sentences plus the ''If... then...'' connective are the Simple
Conditionals, and those that cannot be thus analyzed are called
''Counterfactual'' Conditionals, for lack of a better term.

Chapter Two (Theories of Simple Conditionals) develops an exposition
of several proposals already mentioned in Chapter one.  Briefly,
Simple Conditionals may be regarded as always having a truth-value, or
as not (or not always) having a truth-value.  If Simple Conditionals
are regarded as truth-functional, then they are not always assertible,
even in cases when they are true.  That is, if we take the logic
conditional (also called the material condition, or material
implication) as the description of the truth- values of the Simple
Conditional, then we need another parameter, that of assertibility, to
account for the divergence between truth and use.  At least two
problems arise in connection with the notion of assertibility: it
seems to be especially difficult to state for conditionals, and it is
also difficult to distinguish from the acceptability of the utterance
containing conditionals.  Five theories for handling the matter are
then presented and discussed in a preliminary way.  Very briefly, they
are:

i) Simple Conditionals (in natural language) have truth- values in the
same the way material conditions (in formal logic) do, and the
difference between the truth-values of Simple Conditionals and their
assertibility is explained in terms of pragmatics.

(ii) Simple Conditionals have truth-values in the same the way
material conditions do, and the difference between truth-value and
assertibility is a difference in meaning.

(iii) Simple Conditionals have truth-values, but not always, and do
not follow the truth-table for material conditions, but rather:

- when P and Q are both true, ''If P then Q'' is true

- when they are both false, ''If P then Q'' is false

- otherwise, there is no truth-value.

This is a consequence of regarding ''If P then Q'' as a conditional
assertion, that is, an assertion of Q on the condition that P.  If P
is not the case, there is no assertion, and no truth-value.

(iv) Simple Conditionals have truth values but are not
truth-functional.  The truth of the material condition may be
necessary but not sufficient for the truth of the conditional.  ''If P
then Q'' is regarded as a metalinguistic assertion.

(v) Simple Conditionals lack truth-values altogether.

Problems and inadequacies of each theory are also discussed.

Chapter Three (Ramsey's Test and Adam's Hypothesis) is dedicated, as
the titles states, to discussing two approaches already mentioned.
Ramsey and later Adams discussed the form ''If P then Q'' as an
assertion of Q on the condition that P.  Thus, someone accepting that
Q on the condition that P is described as making minimal revisions in
his or her stock of beliefs, and conditionals are then regarded as
epistemic.  The notion of minimal revision, and the calculus of
conditional probability are then discussed.  According to Woods,
Adams's Hypothesis seems to give a better account (better than, for
example, the use of the notion of relevance) of the behavior of
conditionals in certain troublesome cases.  The troublesome cases
would be the failure of Simple Conditions to comply with transitivity,
contraposition, strengthening of the antecedent, the equivalence of
''P or Q'' with ''not If P then Q'', and with modus tollens.

Chapter Four (Simple Conditionals and Truth-Values: Some Proposals)
brings a review of what has been studied so far, and narrows down the
available options for treating Simple Conditionals.  Woods discusses
Adams's Hypothesis still further, and also Lewis's epistemic approach,
Jackson's notion of robustness, and Grice's pragmatic approach.

Chapter Five (Conditionals and Possible Worlds).  In Chapter one,
Woods denied the usual characterization of ''Counterfactual''
Conditionals as those that imply the falsity of the antecedent. In
this chapter, he applies a widespread approach to counterfactuality
(possible worlds), due mainly to the work of Lewis and Stalnaker, to
the analysis of Simple Conditionals.  Woods discusses the apparatus of
possible worlds, the problem of ordering and selecting worlds, and the
solutions given by Lewis and Stalnaker.  The application of possible
worlds to Simple Conditions gives a good explanation to a wide variety
of cases, but brings several other problems into the field, like the
adequacy of the notion of similarity between worlds, and whether the
choice of worlds should be guided by causal laws (as proposed by
Bennett) and not by similarity.  Even if we accept an approach based
on possible worlds, it cannot give a proper explanation to the reasons
we have for using conditionals the way we do.  It does not seem
possible to explain why the form of Simple Conditional should be
attached to the meaning it has, and it seems to be misguided to apply
a possible world treatment to Simple Conditionals.

Chapter Six (Compound Conditionals and Truth-Values) examines four
types of case in which a conditional is embedded in a larger sentence.
Woods presents his arguments for preferring to regard conditionals as
conditional assertions, lacking truth-values.  The four cases are:

(i) a conditional consequent

(ii) a conditional with disjunctive antecedents

(iii) a disjunction of conditionals

(iv) a conditional with a conditional antecedent, and the negation of
a conditional, which present the greatest problems.

Chapter Seven (Theory of Simple Conditionals; Non- Assertoric
Conditionals) states the two remaining approaches for conditionals:

(i) Simple Conditionals do not have truth-values.  They are used to
make conditional assertions

(ii) Simple Conditionals do have truth-values, but they are relative
to the epistemic state of the speaker.

The second view, however, may be regarded as leading to greater
complexity and not offering any advantages in turn, and the author
prefers to consider Simple Conditionals as lacking truth-values.  They
are used to make conditional assertions, and one extra advantage of
this point of view is the possibility of describing non-assertoric
conditionals (questions and commands) as parallel cases.

Chapter Eight (Sketch of a Theory of ''Counterfactual'' Conditionals)
offers an account of the ''Counterfactual'' Conditionals in terms of
epistemic states of the speaker, as it was already presented in
chapters three and four, concerning Simple Conditionals.  This
approach should allow us to account for several types of sentences
that are not usually grouped with the ''Counterfactual'' type.  It
accommodates the problems of temporal asymmetry, ordering of worlds,
choosing of worlds, and also the detailed interplay between the tense
of verb used and the interpretation of the sentence.  The concluding
remarks stress once more the fact that even if possible worlds are
adequate to describe the form of this kind of conditionals, they
cannot help us to explain the use we make of conditionals, and give
too much attention to ''fantasies'' devoid of more immediate practical
reasons.

The Commentary by Dorothy Edgington takes up roughly one third of the
book.  It is a detailed response to several of the topics of the book,
providing, as Dorothy Edgington says, background for some of the ideas
presented, extra arguments in favor of some positions, and even some
disagreement (concerning the treatment of ''will'' sentences).

Comments

An obvious drawback of this book is that it was left incomplete, and
the text is rather packed, with a lot of theory pressed together.  At
least one section is incomplete: Chapter seven, on compound
conditionals.  Also, the titles of the chapters do not strictly
correspond to the subjects presented in them: the discussion goes far
beyond what is mentioned in the title, and that is a little
misleading.  And the reader, however sympathetic to the cause, could
probably use some more examples, for the subject is indeed a hard one.
Then there are the good aspects: for a book that was left incomplete,
this is an exceptionally clear and well-written one, especially one on
such a demanding subject.  Each new chapter (apart from the first)
begins with a summary of the ideas discussed in the preceding one, and
ends with a sketch of what will be presented in the next, thus making
it a very readable essay, and not at all a collection of loose
theories.  For the beginner in the field, the footnotes provide a good
introduction to the literature on the subject.  Also on the plus side
are the Editor's notes and the Commentary.  In this rather small book,
then, Michael Woods managed to present us with a good map of the area:
a definition of conditionals, a sketch of the reasons why they are so
difficult to deal with, a survey of the main theories proposed to sort
them out, and some fresh proposals of his own, which is reason enough
for us to read and enjoy his book.

ABOUT THE REVIEWER

Maria Leonor Santos teaches Linguistics at Federal University of
Paraíba, Brazil, and is now working for her thesis on conditionals
(in Brazilian Portuguese) at Federal University of Santa Catarina.
Her main interests are Logic, Lexical Semantics, and History of
Linguistics.


---------------------------------------------------------------------------

If you buy this book please tell the publisher or author
that you saw it reviewed on the LINGUIST list.

---------------------------------------------------------------------------
LINGUIST List: Vol-14-3050



More information about the LINGUIST mailing list