32.2374, Review: Cognitive Science; Ling & Literature; Philosophy of Language; Psycholinguistics: Zacks (2020)

The LINGUIST List linguist at listserv.linguistlist.org
Wed Jul 14 04:51:23 UTC 2021


LINGUIST List: Vol-32-2374. Wed Jul 14 2021. ISSN: 1069 - 4875.

Subject: 32.2374, Review: Cognitive Science; Ling & Literature; Philosophy of Language; Psycholinguistics: Zacks (2020)

Moderator: Malgorzata E. Cavar (linguist at linguistlist.org)
Student Moderator: Jeremy Coburn, Lauren Perkins
Managing Editor: Becca Morris
Team: Helen Aristar-Dry, Everett Green, Sarah Robinson, Nils Hjortnaes, Joshua Sims, Billy Dickson
Jobs: jobs at linguistlist.org | Conferences: callconf at linguistlist.org | Pubs: pubs at linguistlist.org

Homepage: http://linguistlist.org

Please support the LL editors and operation with a donation at:
           https://funddrive.linguistlist.org/donate/

Editor for this issue: Jeremy Coburn <jecoburn at linguistlist.org>
================================================================


Date: Wed, 14 Jul 2021 00:50:27
From: Marta Donazzan [Marta.donazzan at univ-Nantes.fr]
Subject: Ten Lectures on the Representation of Events in Language, Perception, Memory, and Action Control

 
Discuss this message:
http://linguistlist.org/pubs/reviews/get-review.cfm?subid=36664197


Book announced at http://linguistlist.org/issues/31/31-735.html

AUTHOR: Jeffrey M. Zacks
TITLE: Ten Lectures on the Representation of Events in Language, Perception, Memory, and Action Control
SERIES TITLE: Distinguished Lectures in Cognitive Linguistics
PUBLISHER: Brill
YEAR: 2020

REVIEWER: Marta Donazzan, Laboratoire de Linguistique de Nantes (UMR 6310)

SUMMARY

This book is the collection of the ten lectures that Jeffery Zacks gave in
December 2017 as the forum speaker at the “17th China International Forum on
Cognitive Linguistics”in Beijing. It consists of a transcript of the lectures,
with no audio-visual material included. Original audio-recordings and
supplementary material have been made available online and may be accessed on
the website figshare.com via a QR code. The book, and its associated online
material, are a good introduction for all students and scholars specialising
in linguistics and interested in understanding the interface between
linguistic and cognitive representations. Although the format of the book – a
collection of lectures – may sometimes give rise to a certain incongruence,
this volume is surprisingly well-structured, as the author progresses through
the lectures in explaining the theory in a coherent way. More importantly, the
relevance of this publication is to be seen in the more general enterprise
taken up by experimental semantics in recent years, which is to allow
experimental work to discriminate among equally plausible theoretical options
and to substantiate formal representations by giving cognitive content to
logical variables or other abstract objects. In this perspective, this small
volume is a welcome contribution for theorists and experimentalists alike, and
an additional step toward realising the goal set by experimental semantics.

EVALUATION

Since its early days, cognitive linguistics has been evolving from its
original place at the crossroads of philosophy, psychology, and semantics to
embrace more formal approaches to language. As regards the representation of
events in language, the renewed interest in cognitive approaches is witnessed
by the vast amount of recent work on causal relations, aspectual modification,
and quantification in event semantics (cf. Truswell 2019 for an overview).
Following this thread, in this review I will try to highlight the points in
Zacks's lectures that answer more specifically some of the most urgent
questions addressed by formal linguistics (and in particular formal semantics
and syntax) to the topic of event representation. The review is built around a
selection of these questions, which may serve as a guide for the reader
interested in specific issues; at the same time, by highlighting theoretical
issues I will try to show how the work by Jeffrey Zacks and his colleagues
provides a possible way of addressing them from the point of view of cognitive
psychology. 

What is an event?

There is a common knowledge and a shared intuition about what an event is. It
is something that happens, and as such has a temporal dimension. It also
happens to something or someone, and as such it has participants. Philosophers
struggled for decades to frame these intuitions in coherent theories in which
linguists have shown a keen interest because of the difficulty inherent in
formally defining  such an object. Empirical evidence sometimes suggests 
considering events as logical individuals (Davidson 1967), sometimes treating
them as properties of time (Vendler 1967, Verkuyl 1999, a.o.). As Zacks
correctly reminds us in his first lecture, however, one of the most pressing
questions that arise when looking at the philosophical literature is this:
which theories are going to be useful for cognitive science, for linguistics,
and for psychology? Research in psychology points to an answer: an event seems
to be perceived as a structured representation, that is, as a “segment of time
at a given location that is conceived by an observer as having a beginning and
an end”. Beginning and end coincide with changes in the most relevant
properties of an event. But what are these? In a series of experiments the
results of which are commented on in these lectures, Zacks and his colleagues
have shown that the properties more likely to be perceived and associated with
the individuality of an event are those that help us to build an internal
coherence in what we see. This is the basis for the actual hypothesis advanced
in Event Segmentation Theory: humans recognise event boundaries by building
models (representations of interactions in a spatio-temporal framework) from
the events they have experienced, and by anticipating what they are
experiencing. Models are then updated regularly in case we make bad
predictions. There are two main features of Event Segmentation Theory that I
would like to point out. 

First, the theory says that our ability to recognise events is rooted in the
adaptive comprehension system of human cognition, which is forward-oriented.
By making predictions about what they are going to see, humans can filter out
everything regular and persistent from the crammed set of data that our
sensory organs register in real time, and they can focus on outstanding
things, keeping track of changes to the regular behaviour of things.

Second, as it is made clear in the third lecture, the theory makes a claim
also about the way in which we learn to do this, which is “in the same way
that we learn to comprehend spoken language: by being immersed in it.” What
Zacks seems to be suggesting here is that the segmentation of events is
acquired through a bootstrapping process akin to that responsible for the
prosodic bootstrapping that, according to certain acquisition theories, leads
to the segmentation of syntactic units in language acquisition (see Soderstorm
et al. 2003). These two assumptions put together inscribe Event Segmentation
Theory within the theoretical background shared by some of the most followed
linguistic theories, and confirm the psychological stance on language from the
point of view of a cognitive scientist.

Segmentation and plurality – how many events?

There is, finally, a third issue. The issue of the identity of events is a
delicate one – identity and individuation are a prerequisite for metaphysical
properties, such as persistence, and for building abstract logical objects,
such as pluralities. As pointed out by Truswell (2019), once we have a theory
providing us with a set of mereological relations (as in e.g. Link 1983), from
a logical point of view nothing prevents us from generating arbitrary events,
by decomposing and recomposing the primitive individuals into arbitrary sets.
The issue, then, is “to complement this logic with a characterisation of
cognitively relevant events” (Truswell 2019: 96).  

Studies investigating the segmentation of events in narratives (expounded in
particular in Lecture Four) point out that, in a default situation (i.e., when
our attention is not channeled in a specific way), the properties more likely
to be perceived as relevant to building an event model mainly concern  the
participants and the temporal continuity of an event (with spatial contiguity
a less salient criterion). What does this mean, more specifically, for
linguists concerned with representing events in language? The issue of
temporal contiguity and change has been evoked, for instance, in the attempt
to motivate the linguistic relevance of distinct aspectual categories
according to which verbal predicates may be classified. While certain events
(such as playing, sleeping, or laughing) may naturally persist in time without
change, and thus are treated as single occurrences, others (such as breaking a
glass or writing a letter) necessarily reach a point after which they cease to
be describable as the same event.  Also, some activities (jumping) can be
understood as events persisting in time or as collections of similar events
(semelfactive events – like multiple occurrences of making a jump), and in
this case, the (absence of) change that makes a plurality of events one single
event is probably in the eye of the beholder. 

How are events treated by grammar?

Finally, Zacks suggests that, keeping the mapping from mind to language as
direct as possible, the structured kind of representation evidenced by
psychological studies should be translated by a structured predication. There
are different models of predicative structure out in the linguistic world –
the baseline being that events, as logical objects, may be conceived of as
relations between individuals, which, when happening, leave a temporal trace.
Formal linguists then developed models where individuals and time are linked
to events by functional elements – individuals by thematic roles and time by
the homomorphic function whose value is the running time of the event (see
e.g. Krifka 1992 for a formal semantic representation). Evidence from
cognitive psychology seems to support the theoretical and formal models
developed by linguists, but once again, experimental methods may be seen as
pivotal in discriminating among theoretical hypotheses. In particular, Zacks
and colleagues argue that their results are best represented formally within
the models developed in the framework of situation semantics (Perry & Barwise
1983). But of course several questions are still pending: how many thematic
roles do we need, and how should each role be characterised? Other studies
grounded in cognitive psychology may help answer these questions (see e.g. the
approach developed by Wolff 2007 and subsequent work, based on psychological
theories of causation). The work resumed by Zack in this volume, however, has
the merit of showing the relevance of such a question for embedding cognition
into grammar.

REFERENCES

Davidson, D. (1967) The logical form of action sentences. In N. Rescher (ed)
“The Logic of Decision and Action”, 81-95. University of Pittsburgh Press.

Krifka, M. (1992) Thematic relations as links between nominal reference and
temporal constitution. In I. Sag and A. Szabolcsi (eds) “Lexical matters”.
Stanford  , CSLI

Link, G. (1983) The logical analysis of plurals and mass terms. A
lattice-theoretical approach. In Bäuerle, Schwarze & von Stechow (eds)
“Meaning, Use and the Interpretation of Language”, 303-323. Berlin  : de
Gruyter. 

Perry, J. & J. Barwise (1983) “Situations and Attitudes”. MIT Press.


ABOUT THE REVIEWER

Marta Donazzan is lecturer of Linguistics at the University of Nantes, and
researcher at the Laboratoire de Linguistique de Nantes (LLING/ UMR 6310).
After receiving her PhD in Linguistics at the University of Paris 7 in 2008,
she worked as a lecturer and a researcher in various institutions in France
and Germany. Her interests are in formal semantics and the interface between
cognition and grammar.





------------------------------------------------------------------------------

***************************    LINGUIST List Support    ***************************
 The 2020 Fund Drive is under way! Please visit https://funddrive.linguistlist.org
  to find out how to donate and check how your university, country or discipline
     ranks in the fund drive challenges. Or go directly to the donation site:
                   https://crowdfunding.iu.edu/the-linguist-list

                        Let's make this a short fund drive!
                Please feel free to share the link to our campaign:
                    https://funddrive.linguistlist.org/donate/
 


----------------------------------------------------------
LINGUIST List: Vol-32-2374	
----------------------------------------------------------






More information about the LINGUIST mailing list