Deixis, Buhler and the Problem of Ambiguity
Tom Givon
tgivon at uoregon.edu
Mon May 18 16:39:46 UTC 2009
I think that before we accept as gospel the idea that "from the infant's
point of view, deixis is as confusing as a hall of mirrors", we ought
perhaps look a bit more carefully at how infants actually acquire
communicative expression of reference, starting from deixis and going on
to other kinds of reference. The CHILDES transcript of communication in
the first year of life shows that the prerequisite to reference is the
care-giver's intense exercise in establishing JOINT ATTENTION. The
reason why this will become first deictic reference is obvious--in early
childhood, all communication is about here-and-now, you-and-I,
this-and-that accessible to both of us in the shared speech situation.
There is nothing confusing to the infant in these learning sessions. On
the contrary, the process capitalizes on the shared perceptual field and
the child's innate propensity to attend to salient objects--colorful,
compactly-shaped, fast-moving, or pointed to by the care-giver. But the
child is also acquiring another important prerequisite to reference--and
communication in general--during the first year of life: Considering
OTHER MINDS as having a perspective distinct from one's own
(inter-subjectivity; theory of mind). So the acquisition of referential
communication is deeply embedded in these early capacities.
Joint-attention sessions are indeed early theory-of-mind instructional
sessions.
Attracting the child attention to a referent within the shared situation
in early childhood is done by various pointing means--touching,
approaching, holding-bringing-and-showing, changing the child's
position, pointing, and eventually verbal deictic expressions. Verbs of
perception such as "see", "look", "ear" or "touch" are prominently used
in the care-giver's verbal "obligato" that accompanies these
joint-attention (or joint-reference) sessions. Early nominal vocabulary
is also prominently introduced at these sessions. And early uses of
determiners ('this', 'the', 'your', 'my') that are not motivated by
discourse but still by the deictic situation.
With the gradual change during the second year to communication about
non-present objects and future and past events, the move from deictic to
other types of reference is phased in, together with more sophisticated
grammatical devices that point at remembered or imagined referents.
Thus, while the domain of reference expands, the basic principle
established in early infancy--JOINT-ATTENTION--remains as the leitmotif
of all referential gestures, verbal & otherwise: Make sure that you & I
are attending to the same thing. This is, of course, deeply embedded in
the human capacity to consider other minds ("inter-subjectivity, Theory
of Mind, empathy). There is a beautiful recent book by Sarah Hrdy on the
evolution of this capacity ("Mother & Others") that I think is perhaps
worth reviewing here, maybe later. (And Ch. 8 "How children acquire
complex reference" of my recent "The Genesis of Syntactic Complexity"
deals in some detail with the child reference data during years 2-3-4).
Cheers, TG
==============
In more sophisticated referential learning during the 2nd and 3rd year,
Salinas17 at aol.com wrote:
> In a message dated 5/18/09 3:17:34 AM, twood at uwc.ac.za writes:
> --I agree with the broad notion of deixis; I have never thought of it as a early stages ("see the kitty?").
> small class of linguistic expressions. But I don't agree that it has much to
> do with ambiguity. It seems to me that deixis is more like the pole of
> concrete as opposed to abstract in language, or specific as opposed to
> universal. So a linguistic expression will tend to have a deictic content as well as
> an ideational content--
>
> Tahir - Thanks for the comment. Let me suggest that ambiguity arises in
> two ways with deixis. One is the simple problem created by external
> context. Levinson describes these on all levels, but the most apparent are the
> most basic -- "from the infantâs point of view, deixis is as confusing as a
> hall of mirrors: my âIâ is your âyouâ, my âthisâ is your âthatâ, my âhereâ
> , your âthereâ, and so forth."
>
> Ambiguity is also involved with deixis when we use it to be definite, i.e.,
> to minimize ambiguity -- I don't want any car but this car. The irony
> here is that what decreases ambiguity also increases ambiguity, since we are
> not in Kansas anymore when we accept deictic reference into our study of
> expression.
>
> The problem I cited with deixis applying to abstracts is that we really
> have no way of stopping the ball at just concretes. For example:
> John knew that.
> That was exactly what I was thinking.
> Do you believe this?
> Here is where we part thinking.
> That is diectic and this is not.
> Here, on the other hand, a squared times b squared equals d.
>
> So-called secondary deixis apparently can apply to extreme abstracts --
> which is why perhaps Buhler limited deixis to the point before the "pointing"
> became representation or symbolic. Perhaps because the process changes
> after that, if we are pointing to an abstract.
>
> regards and thanks,
> steve long
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
> **************
> A Good Credit Score is 700 or Above. See Yours in Just 2 Easy
> Steps!
> (http://pr.atwola.com/promoclk/100126575x1221322941x1201367178/aol?redir=http://www.freecreditreport.com/pm/default.aspx?sc=668072&hmpgID=115&
> bcd=Mayfooter51809NO115)
>
>
More information about the Funknet
mailing list